[p.272]
Appendix to Chapter 19
PROFESSOR PIGOU'S "THEORY OF UNEMPLOYMENT"
Professor Pigou in his Theory of
Unemployment makes the volume of employment to depend on two fundamental
factors, namely (1) the real rates of wages for which workpeople stipulate, and
(2) the shape of the Real Demand Function for Labour. The central sections of
his book are concerned with determining the shape of the latter function. The
fact that workpeople in fact stipulate, not for a real rate of wages, but for a
money-rate, is not ignored; but, in effect, it is assumed that the actual
money-rate of wages divided by the price of wage-goods can be taken to measure
the real rate demanded.
The equations which, as he says, "form the starting point of the enquiry"
into the Real Demand Function for Labour are given in his Theory of
Unemployment, p. 90. Since the tacit assumptions, which govern the
application of his analysis, slip in near the outset of his argument, I will
summarise his treatment up to the crucial point.
Professor Pigou divides industries into those "engaged in making wage-goods
at home and in making exports the sale of which creates claims to wage-goods
abroad" and the "other" industries: which it is convenient to call the
wage-goods industries and the non-wage-goods industries respectively. He
supposes x men to be employed in the former and y men in the
latter. The output in value of wage-goods of the x men he calls F(x);
and the general rate of wages F'(x). This, though he does not stop
to mention it, is tantamount to assuming that marginal wage-cost is equal to
marginal prime cost.[1]
Further, he assumes [p.273] that x + y = f(x),
i.e. that the number of men employed in the wage-goods industries is a
function of total employment. He then shows that the elasticity of the real
demand for labour in the aggregate (which gives us the shape of our quaesitum,
namely the Real Demand Function for Labour) can be written
f'(x) F'(x)
Er = ¾¾¾ · ¾¾¾¾
f(x) F"(x)
So far as notation goes, there is no significant difference between this and
my own modes of expression. In so far as we can identify Professor Pigou's
wage-goods with my consumption-goods, and his "other goods" with my
investment-goods, it follows that his F(x) / F'(x),
being the value of the output of the wage-goods industries in terms of the
wage-unit, is the same as my Cw. Furthermore, his
function f is (subject to the identification of
wage-goods with consumption-goods) a function of what I have called above the
employment multiplier k'. For
Dx = k'Dy,
1
so that f'(x) = 1 + ¾¾.
k'
Thus Professor Pigou's "elasticity of the real demand for labour in the
aggregate" is a concoction similar to some of my own, depending partly on the
physical and technical conditions in industry (as given by his function F)
and partly on the propensity to consume wage-goods (as given by his function f);
provided always that we are limiting ourselves to the special case where
marginal labour-cost is equal to marginal prime cost.
To determine the quantity of employment, Professor Pigou [p.274] then
combines with his "real demand for labour", a supply function for labour. He
assumes that this is a function of the real wage and of nothing else. But, as he
has also assumed that the real wage is a function of the number of men x
who are employed in the wage-goods industries, this amounts to assuming that the
total supply of labour at the existing real wage is a function of x and
of nothing else. That is to say, n = c(x),
where n is the supply of labour available at a real wage F'(x).
Thus, cleared of all complication, Professor Pigou's analysis amounts to an
attempt to discover the volume of actual employment from the equations
x + y = f(x)
and n = c(x).
But there are here three unknowns and only two equations. It seems clear that
he gets round this difficulty by taking n = x + y.
This amounts, of course, to assuming that there is no involuntary unemployment
in the strict sense, i.e. that all labour available at the existing real
wage is in fact employed. In this case x has the value which satisfies
the equation
f(x) = c(x);
and when we have thus found that the value of x is equal to (say) n1,
y must be equal to c(n1) - n1,
and total employment n is equal to c(n1).
It is worth pausing for a moment to consider what this involves. It means
that, if the supply function of labour changes, more labour being available at a
given real wage (so that n1 + dn1
is now the value of x which satisfies the equation f(x) = c(x)),
the demand for the output of the non-wage-goods industries is such that
employment in these industries is bound to increase by just the amount which
will preserve equality between f(n1 + dn1)
and c(n1 + dn1).
The only other way in which it is possible for aggregate employment to change is
through a modification of the propensity to purchase wage-goods and
non-wage-goods respectively such that there is an increase of y
accompanied by a greater decrease of x.
The assumption that n = x + y
means, of course, that labour is always in a position to determine its own real
wage. Thus, the assumption that labour is in a position to determine its own
real wage, means that the demand for the output of the non-wage-goods industries
obeys the above laws. In other words, it is assumed that the rate of interest
always adjusts itself to the schedule of the marginal efficiency of capital in
such a way as to [p.275] preserve full employment. Without this
assumption Professor Pigou's analysis breaks down and provides no means of
determining what the volume of employment will be. It is, indeed, strange that
Professor Pigou should have supposed that he could furnish a theory of
unemployment which involves no reference at all to changes in the rate of
investment (i.e. to changes in employment in the non-wage-goods
industries) due, not to a change in the supply function of labour, but to
changes in (e.g.) either the rate of interest or the state of confidence.
His title the "Theory of Unemployment" is, therefore, something of a
misnomer. His book is not really concerned with this subject. It is a discussion
of how much employment there will be, given the supply function of labour, when
the conditions for full employment are satisfied. The purpose of the concept of
the elasticity of the real demand for labour in the aggregate is to show by how
much full employment will rise or fall corresponding to a given shift in
the supply function of labour. Or¾alternatively and
perhaps better¾we may regard his book as a
non-causative investigation into the functional relationship which determines
what level of real wages will correspond to any given level of employment. But
it is not capable of telling us what determines the actual level of
employment; and on the problem of involuntary unemployment it has no direct
bearing.
If Professor Pigou were to deny the possibility of involuntary unemployment
in the sense in which I have defined it above, as, perhaps, he would, it is
still difficult to see how his analysis could be applied. For his omission to
discuss what determines the connection between x and y, i.e.
between employment in the wage-goods and non-wage-goods industries respectively,
still remains fatal.
Moreover, he agrees that within certain limits labour in fact often
stipulates, not for a given real wage, but for a given money-wage. But in this
case the supply function of labour is not a function of F'(x)
alone but also of the money-price of wage-goods;¾with
the result that the previous analysis breaks down and an additional factor has
to be introduced, without there being an additional equation to provide for this
additional unknown. The pitfalls of a pseudo-mathematical method, which can make
no progress except by making everything a function of a single variable and
assuming that all the partial differentials vanish, could not be better
illustrated. For it is no good to admit later on that there are in fact other
variables, and yet to proceed [p.276] without re-writing everything that
has been written up to that point. Thus if (within limits) it is a money-wage
for which labour stipulates, we still have insufficient data, even if we assume
that n = x + y, unless we
know what determines the money-price of wage-goods. For, the money-price of
wage-goods will depend on the aggregate amount of employment. Therefore we
cannot say what aggregate employment will be, until we know the money-price of
wage-goods; and we cannot know the money-price of wage-goods until we know the
aggregate amount of employment. We are, as I have said, one equation short. Yet
it might be a provisional assumption of a rigidity of money-wages, rather than
of real wages, which would bring our theory nearest to the facts. For example,
money-wages in Great Britain during the turmoil and uncertainty and wide price
fluctuations of the decade 1924-1934 were stable
within a range of 6 per cent, whereas real wages fluctuated by more than 20 per
cent. A theory cannot claim to be a general theory, unless it is
applicable to the case where (or the range within which) money-wages are fixed,
just as much as to any other case. Politicians are entitled to complain that
money-wages ought to be highly flexible; but a theorist must be prepared
to deal indifferently with either state of affairs. A scientific theory cannot
require the facts to conform to its own assumptions.
When Professor Pigou comes to deal expressly with the effect of a reduction
of money-wages, he again, palpably (to my mind), introduces too few data to
permit of any definite answer being obtainable. He begins by rejecting the
argument (op. cit. p. 101) that, if marginal prime cost is equal to
marginal wage-cost, non-wage-earners' incomes will be altered, when money-wages
are reduced, in the same proportion as wage-earners', on the ground that this is
only valid, if the quantity of employment remains unaltered¾which
is the very point under discussion. But he proceeds on the next page (op. cit.
p. 102) to make the same mistake himself by taking as his assumption that "at
the outset nothing has happened to non-wage-earners money-income", which, as he
has just shown, is only valid if the quantity of employment does not remain
unaltered-which is the very point under discussion In fact, no answer is
possible, unless other factors are included in our data.
The manner in which the admission, that labour in fact stipulates for a given
money-wage and not for a given real wage (provided that the real wage does not
fall below a certain minimum), affects the analysis, can also be shown by
pointing out [p.277] that in this case the assumption that more labour is
not available except at a greater real wage, which is fundamental to most of the
argument, breaks down. For example, Professor Pigou rejects (op. cit. p. 75)
the theory of the multiplier by assuming that the rate of real wages is given, i.e.
that, there being already full employment, no additional labour is forthcoming
at a lower real wage. Subject to this assumption, the argument is, of course,
correct. But in this passage Professor Pigou is criticising a proposal relating
to practical policy; and it is fantastically far removed from the facts to
assume, at a time when statistical unemployment in Great Britain exceeded
2,000,000 (i.e. when there were 2,000,000 men willing to work at the
existing money-wage), that any rise in the cost of living, however moderate,
relatively to the money-wage would cause the withdrawal from the labour market
of more than the equivalent of all these 2,000,000 men.
It is important to emphasise that the whole of Professor Pigou's book is
written on the assumption that any rise in the cost of living, however
moderate, relatively to the money-wage will cause the withdrawal from the labour
market of a number of workers greater than that of all the existing unemployed.
Moreover, Professor Pigou does not notice in this passage (op. cit. p. 75)
that the argument, which he advances against "secondary" employment as a result
of public works, is, on the same assumptions, equally fatal to increased "primary"
employment from the same policy. For if the real rate of wages ruling in the
wage-goods industries is given, no increased employment whatever is possible¾except,
indeed, as a result of non-wage-earners reducing their consumption of
wage-goods. For those newly engaged in the primary employment will presumably
increase their consumption of wage-goods which will reduce the real wage and
hence (on his assumptions) lead to a withdrawal of labour previously employed
elsewhere. Yet Professor Pigou accepts, apparently, the possibility of increased
primary employment. The line between primary and secondary employment seems to
be the critical psychological point at which his good common sense ceases to
overbear his bad theory.
The difference in the conclusions to which the above differences in
assumptions and in analysis lead can be shown by the following important passage
in which Professor Pigou sums up his point of view: "With perfectly free
competition among workpeople and labour perfectly mobile, the nature of the
relation (i.e. between the real wage-rates for which people stipulate [p.278]
and the demand function for labour) will be very simple. There will always be at
work a strong tendency for wage-rates to be so related to demand that everybody
is employed. Hence, in stable conditions everyone will actually be employed. The
implication is that such unemployment as exists at any time is due wholly to the
fact that changes in demand conditions are continually taking place and that
frictional resistances prevent the appropriate wage adjustments from being made
instantaneously."[1]
He concludes (op. cit. p. 253) that unemployment is primarily due
to a wage policy which fails to adjust itself sufficiently to changes in the
real demand function for labour.
Thus Professor Pigou believes that in the long run unemployment can be cured
by wage adjustments;[2] whereas I
maintain that the real wage (subject only to a minimum set by the marginal
disutility of employment) is not primarily determined by "wage adjustments"
(though these may have repercussions) but by the other forces of the system,
some of which (in particular the relation between the schedule of the marginal
efficiency of capital and the rate of interest) Professor Pigou has failed, if I
am right, to include in his formal scheme.
Finally, when Professor Pigou comes to the "Causation of Unemployment" he
speaks, it is true, of fluctuations in the state of demand, much as I do. But he
identifies the state of demand with the Real Demand Function for Labour,
forgetful of how narrow a thing the latter is on his definition. For the Real
Demand Function for Labour depends by definition (as we have seen above) on nothing
but two factors, namely (1) the relationship in any given environment
between the total number of men employed and the number who have to be employed
in the wage-goods industries to provide them with what they consume, and (2) the
state of marginal productivity in the wage-goods industries. Yet in Part V. of
his Theory of Unemployment fluctuations in the state of "the real demand
for labour" are given a position of importance. The "real demand for labour" is
regarded as a factor which is susceptible of wide short-period fluctuations (op.
cit. Part V., chaps. vi.-xii.), and the
suggestion seems to be that swings in "the real demand for labour" are, in
combination with the failure of wage policy to respond sensitively to such
changes, largely responsible for the trade cycle. To the reader all this seems,
at first, reasonable [p.279] and familiar. For, unless he goes back to
the definition, "fluctuations in the real demand for labour" will convey to his
mind the same sort of suggestion as I mean to convey by "fluctuations in the
state of aggregate demand". But if we go back to the definition of the "real
demand for labour", all this loses its plausibility. For we shall find that
there is nothing in the world less likely to be subject to sharp short-period
swings than this factor.
Professor Pigou's "real demand for labour" depends, by definition, on nothing
but F(x), which represents the physical conditions of production
in the wage-goods industries, and f(x), which
represents the functional relationship between employment in the wage-goods
industries and total employment corresponding to any given level of the latter.
It is difficult to see a reason why either of these functions should change,
except gradually over a long period. Certainly there seems no reason to suppose
that they are likely to fluctuate during a trade cycle. For F(x) can only
change slowly, and, in a technically progressive community, only in the forward
direction; whilst f(x) will remain stable,
unless we suppose a sudden outbreak of thrift in the working classes, or, more
generally, a sudden shift in the propensity to consume. I should expect,
therefore, that the real demand for labour would remain virtually constant
throughout a trade cycle. I repeat that Professor Pigou has altogether omitted
from his analysis the unstable factor, namely fluctuations in the scale of
investment, which is most often at the bottom of the phenomenon of fluctuations
in employment.
I have criticised at length Professor Pigou's theory of unemployment not
because he seems to me to be more open to criticism than other economists of the
classical school; but because his is the only attempt with which I am acquainted
to write down the classical theory of unemployment precisely. Thus it has been
incumbent on me to raise my objections to this theory in the most formidable
presentment in which it has been advanced.
Footnotes: [p.272] 1 - The source of
the fallacious practice of equating marginal wage-cost to marginal prime cost
may, perhaps, be found in an ambiguity in the meaning of marginal wage-cost.
We might mean by it the cost of an additional unit of output if no additional
cost is incurred except additional wage-cost; or we might mean the additional
wage cost involved in producing and additional unit of output in the most
economical way with the help of the existing equipment and other unemployed
factors. In the former case we are pre-[p.273]cluded from combining
with the additional labour any additional entrepreneurship or working capital or
anything else other than labour which would add to the cost; and we are even
precluded from allowing the additional labour to wear out the equipment any
faster than the smaller labour force would have done. Since in the former
case we have forbidden any element of cost other than labour cost to enter into
marginal prime-cost, it does, of course, follow that marginal wage-cost and
marginal prime-cost, are equal. But the results of an analysis conducted
on this premiss have almost no application, since the assumption on which it is
based is very seldom realised in practice. For we are not so foolish in
practice as to refuse to associate with additional labour appropriate additions
of other factors, in so far as they are available, and the assumption will,
therefore, only apply if we assume that all the factors, other than labour, are
already being employed to the utmost. [back to text] [p.278]
1 - Op. cit. p.252. [back to text] [p.278]
2 - There is no hint or suggestion that this comes
about through reactions on the rate of interest. [back to text]
|