[p.333]
Chapter 23
NOTES ON MERCANTILISM, THE USURY LAWS, STAMPED MONEY AND
THEORIES OF UNDER-CONSUMPTION
I
For some two hundred years both economic theorists and practical men did not
doubt that there is a peculiar advantage to a country in a favourable balance of
trade, and grave danger in an unfavourable balance, particularly if it results
in an efflux of the precious metals. But for the past one hundred years there
has been a remarkable divergence of opinion. The majority of statesmen and
practical men in most countries, and nearly half of them even in Great Britain,
the home of the opposite view, have remained faithful to the ancient doctrine;
whereas almost all economic theorists have held that anxiety concerning such
matters is absolutely groundless except on a very short view, since the
mechanism of foreign trade is self-adjusting and attempts to interfere with it
are not only futile, but greatly impoverish those who practise them because they
forfeit the advantages of the international division of labour. It will be
convenient, in accordance with tradition, to designate the older opinion as Mercantilism
and the newer as Free Trade,
though these terms, since each of them has both a broader and a narrower
signification, must be interpreted with reference to the context.
Generally speaking, modern economists have maintained not merely that there
is, as a rule, a balance of [p.334] gain from the international division
of labour sufficient to outweigh such advantages as mercantilist practice can
fairly claim, but that the mercantilist argument is based, from start to finish,
on an intellectual confusion.
Marshall, [1]
for example, although his references to Mercantilism are not altogether
unsympathetic, had no regard for their central theory as such and does not even
mention those elements of truth in their contentions which I shall examine
below.[2] In the same way, the
theoretical concessions which free-trade economists have been ready to make in
contemporary controversies, relating, for example, to the encouragement of
infant industries or to the improvement of the terms of trade, are not concerned
with the real substance of the mercantilist case. During the fiscal controversy
of the first quarter of the present century I do not remember that any
concession was ever allowed by economists to the claim that Protection might
increase domestic employment. It will be fairest, perhaps, to quote, as an
example, what I wrote myself. So lately
as 1923, as a faithful pupil of the classical
school who did not at that time doubt what he had been taught and
entertained on this matter no reserves at all, I wrote: "If there is one thing
that Protection can not do, it is to cure Unemployment . . .
There are some arguments for Protection, based upon its securing possible but
improbable advantages, to which there is no simple answer. But the claim to cure
Unemployment involves the Protectionist fallacy in its grossest and crudest
form." [3] As for earlier
mercantilist theory, no[p.335] intelligible account was available; and we
were brought up to believe that it was little better than nonsense. So
absolutely overwhelming and complete has been the domination of the classical
school.
II
Let me first state in my own terms what now seems to me to be the element of
scientific truth in mercantilist doctrine. We will then compare this with the
actual arguments of the mercantilists. It should be understood that the
advantages claimed are avowedly national advantages and are unlikely to benefit
the world as a whole.
When a country is growing in wealth somewhat rapidly, the further progress of
this happy state of affairs is liable to be interrupted, in conditions of laissez-faire,
by the insufficiency of the inducements to new investment. Given the social and
political environment and the national characteristics which determine the
propensity to consume, the well-being of a progressive state essentially
depends, for the reasons we have already explained, on the sufficiency of such
inducements. They may be found either in home investment or in foreign
investment (including in the latter the accumulation of the precious metals),
which, between them, make up aggregate investment. In conditions in which the
quantity of aggregate investment is determined by the profit motive alone, the
opportunities for home investment will be governed, in the long run, by the
domestic rate of interest; whilst the volume of foreign investment is
necessarily determined by the size of the favourable balance of trade. Thus, in
a society where there is no question of direct investment under the aegis of
public authority, the economic objects, with which it is reasonable for the
government to be preoccupied, are the domestic rate of interest and the balance
of foreign trade.[p.336]
Now, if the wage-unit is somewhat stable and not liable to spontaneous
changes of significant magnitude (a condition which is almost always satisfied),
if the state of liquidity-preference is somewhat stable, taken as an average of
its short-period fluctuations, and if banking conventions are also stable, the
rate of interest will tend to be governed by the quantity of the precious
metals, measured in terms of the wage-unit, available to satisfy the community's
desire for liquidity. At the same time, in an age in which substantial foreign
loans and the outright ownership of wealth located abroad are scarcely
practicable, increases and decreases in the quantity of the precious metals will
largely depend on whether the balance of trade is favourable or unfavourable.
Thus, as it happens, a preoccupation on the part of the authorities with a
favourable balance of trade served both purposes; and was, furthermore,
the only available means of promoting them. At a time when the authorities had
no direct control over the domestic rate of interest or the other inducements to
home investment, measures to increase the favourable balance of trade were the
only direct means at their disposal for increasing foreign investment;
and, at the same time, the effect of a favourable balance of trade on the influx
of the precious metals was their only indirect means of reducing the
domestic rate of interest and so increasing the inducement to home investment.
There are, however, two limitations on the success of this policy which must
not be overlooked. If the domestic rate of interest falls so low that the volume
of investment is sufficiently stimulated to raise employment to a level which
breaks through some of the critical points at which the wage-unit rises, the
increase in the domestic level of costs will begin to react unfavourably on the
balance of foreign trade, so that the effort to increase the latter will have
overreached and defeated itself. Again, if the domestic rate of interest [p.337]
falls so low relatively to rates of interest elsewhere as to stimulate a volume
of foreign lending which is disproportionate to the favourable balance, there
may ensue an efflux of the precious metals sufficient to reverse the advantages
previously obtained. The risk of one or other of these limitations becoming
operative is increased in the case of a country which is large and
internationally important by the fact that, in conditions where the current
output of the precious metals from the mines is on a relatively small scale, an
influx of money into one country means an efflux from another; so that the
adverse effects of rising costs and falling rates of interest at home may be
accentuated (if the mercantilist policy is pushed too far) by falling costs and
rising rates of interest abroad.
The economic history of Spain in the latter part of the fifteenth and in the
sixteenth centuries provides an example of a country whose foreign trade was
destroyed by the effect on the wage-unit of an excessive abundance of the
precious metals. Great Britain in the pre-war years of the twentieth century
provides an example of a country in which the excessive facilities for foreign
lending and the purchase of properties abroad frequently stood in the way of the
decline in the domestic rate of interest which was required to ensure full
employment at home. The history of India at all times has provided an example of
a country impoverished by a preference for liquidity amounting to so strong a
passion that even an enormous and chronic influx of the precious metals has been
insufficient to bring down the rate of interest to a level which was compatible
with the growth of real wealth.
Nevertheless, if we contemplate a society with a somewhat stable wage-unit,
with national characteristics which determine the propensity to consume and the
preference for liquidity, and with a monetary system which rigidly links the
quantity of money to the stock of the precious metals, it will be essential for
the main-[p.338]tenance of prosperity that the authorities should pay
close attention to the state of the balance of trade. For a favourable balance,
provided it is not too large, will prove extremely stimulating; whilst an
unfavourable balance may soon produce a state of persistent depression.
It does not follow from this that the maximum degree of restriction of
imports will promote the maximum favourable balance of trade. The earlier
mercantilists laid great emphasis on this and were often to be found opposing
trade restrictions because on a long view they were liable to operate adversely
to a favourable balance. It is, indeed, arguable that in the special
circumstances of mid-nineteenth-century Great Britain an almost complete freedom
of trade was the policy most conducive to the development of a favourable
balance. Contemporary experience of trade restrictions in post-war Europe offers
manifold examples of ill-conceived impediments on freedom which, designed to
improve the favourable balance, had in fact a contrary tendency.
For this and other reasons the reader must not reach a premature conclusion
as to the practical policy to which our argument leads up. There are
strong presumptions of a general character against trade restrictions unless
they can be justified on special grounds. The advantages of the international
division of labour are real and substantial, even though the classical school
greatly overstressed them. The fact that the advantage which our own country
gains from a favourable balance is liable to involve an equal disadvantage to
some other country (a point to which the mercantilists were fully alive) means
not only that great moderation is necessary, so that a country secures for
itself no larger a share of the stock of the precious metals than is fair and
reasonable, but also that an immoderate policy may lead to a senseless
international competition for a favourable balance which injures all [p.339] alike.[1]
And finally, a policy of trade restrictions is a treacherous instrument even for
the attainment of its ostensible object, since private interest, administrative
incompetence and the intrinsic difficulty of the task may divert it into
producing results directly opposite to those intended.
Thus, the weight of my criticism is directed against the inadequacy of the theoretical
foundations of the laissez-faire doctrine upon which I was brought up and
which for many years I taught;¾against the notion
that the rate of interest and the volume of investment are self-adjusting at the
optimum level, so that preoccupation with the balance of trade is a waste of
time. For we, the faculty of economists, prove to have been guilty of
presumptuous error in treating as a puerile obsession what for centuries has
been a prime object of practical statecraft.
Under the influence of this faulty theory the City of London gradually
devised the most dangerous technique for the maintenance of equilibrium which
can possibly be imagined, namely, the technique of bank rate coupled with a
rigid parity of the foreign exchanges. For this meant that the objective of
maintaining a domestic rate of interest consistent with full employment was
wholly ruled out. Since, in practice, it is impossible to neglect the balance of
payments, a means of controlling it was evolved which, instead of protecting the
domestic rate of interest, sacrificed it to the operation of blind forces.
Recently, practical bankers in London have learnt much, and one can almost hope
that in Great Britain the technique of bank rate will never be used again to
protect the foreign balance in conditions in which it is likely to cause
unemployment at home.
Regarded as the theory of the individual firm and [p.340] of the
distribution of the product resulting from the employment of a given quantity of
resources, the classical theory has made a contribution to economic thinking
which cannot be impugned. It is impossible to think clearly on the subject
without this theory as a part of one's apparatus of thought. I must not be
supposed to question this in calling attention to their neglect of what was
valuable in their predecessors. Nevertheless, as a contribution to statecraft,
which is concerned with the economic system as a whole and with securing the
optimum employment of the system's entire resources, the methods of the early
pioneers of economic thinking in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries may
have attained to fragments of practical wisdom which the unrealistic
abstractions of Ricardo first forgot
and then obliterated. There was wisdom in their intense preoccupation with
keeping down the rate of interest by means of usury laws (to which we will
return later in this chapter), by maintaining the domestic stock of money and by
discouraging rises in the wage-unit; and in their readiness in the last resort
to restore the stock of money by devaluation, if it had become plainly deficient
through an unavoidable foreign drain, a rise in the wage-unit,[1]
or any other cause.
III
The early pioneers of economic
thinking may have hit upon their maxims of practical wisdom without having had
much cognisance of the underlying theoretical grounds. Let us, therefore,
examine briefly the reasons they gave as well as what they recommended. This is [p.341]
made easy by reference to Professor Heckscher's
great work on Mercantilism, in which the essential characteristics of
economic thought over a period of two centuries are made available for the first
time to the general economic reader. The quotations which follow are mainly
taken from his pages.[1]
(1) Mercantilist [RES] thought
never supposed that there was a self-adjusting tendency by which the rate of
interest would be established at the appropriate level. On the contrary they
were emphatic that an unduly high rate of interest was the main obstacle to the
growth of wealth; and they were even aware that the rate of interest depended on
liquidity-preference and the quantity of money. They were concerned both with
diminishing liquidity-preference and with increasing the quantity of money, and
several of them made it clear that their preoccupation with increasing the
quantity of money was due to their desire to diminish the rate of interest.
Professor Heckscher sums up this aspect of their theory as follows:
The position of the more perspicacious mercantilists was in this respect,
as in many others, perfectly clear within certain limits. For them, money was¾to
use the terminology of to-day¾a factor of
production, on the same footing as land, sometimes regarded as "artificial"
wealth as distinct from the "natural" wealth; interest on capital was the
payment for the renting of money similar to rent for land. In so far as
mercantilists sought to discover objective reasons for the height of the rate
of interest¾and they did so more and more during
this period¾they found such reasons in the total
quantity of money. From the abundant material available, only the most typical
examples will be selected, so as to demonstrate first and foremost how lasting
this notion was, how deep-rooted and independent of practical considerations.
Both of the protagonists in the struggle over monetary [p.342] policy
and the East India trade in the early 1620's in England were in entire
agreement on this point. Gerard Malynes
stated, giving detailed reason for his assertion, that "Plenty of money
decreaseth usury in price or rate" (Lex Mercatoria and Maintenance
of Free Trade, 1622). His truculent and rather unscrupulous adversary,
Edward Misselden, replied that "The
remedy for Usury may be plenty of money" (Free
Trade or the Meanes to make Trade Florish, same year). Of the leading
writers of half a century later, Child,
the omnipotent leader of the East India Company and its most skilful advocate,
discussed (1668)
the question of how far the legal maximum rate of interest, which he
emphatically demanded, would result in drawing "the money" of the Dutch away
from England. He found a remedy for this dreaded disadvantage in the easier
transference of bills of debt, if these were used as currency, for this, he
said, "will certainly supply the defect of at least one-half of all the ready
money we have in use in the nation". Petty,
the other writer, who was entirely unaffected by the clash of interests, was
in agreement with the rest when he explained the "natural" fall in the rate of
interest from 10 per cent to 6 per cent by the increase in the amount of money
(Political
Arithmetick, 1676), and advised lending at interest as an appropriate
remedy for a country with too much "Coin" (Quantulumcunque
concerning Money, 1682).
This reasoning, naturally enough, was by no means confined to England.
Several years later (1701 and 1706), for example, French merchants and
statesmen complained of the prevailing scarcity of coin (disette des espèces)
as the cause of the high interest rates, and they were anxious to lower the
rate of usury by increasing the circulation of money. [1]
The great Locke was, perhaps, the
first to express in abstract terms the relationship between the rate of interest
and the quantity of money in his controversy with Petty.[2]
He was opposing Petty's proposal of a maximum rate of interest on the ground
that it was as impracticable as to fix a maximum rent for land, since "the
natural Value of Money, as it is apt to yield such [p.343] an yearly
Income by Interest, depends on the whole quantity of the then passing Money of
the Kingdom, in proportion to the whole Trade of the Kingdom (i.e. the
general Vent of all the commodities)".[1]
Locke explains that money has two values: (i) its value in use which is given by
the rate of interest and in this it has the Nature of Land, the Income of one
being called Rent, of the other, Use[2]",
and (2) its value in exchange "and in this it has the Nature of a Commodity",
its value in exchange "depending only on the Plenty or Scarcity of Money in
proportion to the Plenty or Scarcity of those things and not on what Interest
shall be". Thus Locke was the parent of twin quantity theories. In the first
place he held that the rate of interest depended on the proportion of the
quantity of money (allowing for the velocity of circulation) to the total value
of trade. In the second place he held that the value of money in exchange
depended on the proportion of the quantity of money to the total volume of goods
in the market. But¾standing with one foot in the
mercantilist world and with one foot in the classical world[3] ¾he
was confused concerning the relation between these two proportions, and he
overlooked altogether the possibility of fluctuations in
liquidity-preference. He was, however, eager to explain that a [p.344] reduction
in the rate of interest has no direct effect on the price-level and
affects prices "only as the Change of Interest in Trade conduces to the bringing
in or carrying out Money or Commodity, and so in time varying their Proportion
here in England from what it was before", i.e. if the reduction in the
rate of interest leads to the export of cash or an increase in output. But he
never, I think, proceeds to a genuine synthesis.[1]
How easily the mercantilist mind distinguished between the rate of interest
and the marginal efficiency of capital is illustrated by a passage (printed in
1621) which Locke quotes from A Letter to a friend concerning Usury: "High
Interest decays Trade. The advantage from Interest is greater than the Profit
from Trade, which makes the rich Merchants give over, and put out their Stock to
Interest, and the lesser Merchants Break." Fortrey
(England's
Interest and Improvement, 1663) affords another example of the stress
laid on a low rate of interest as a means of increasing wealth.
The mercantilists did not overlook the point that, if an excessive
liquidity-preference were to withdraw the influx of precious metals into hoards,
the advantage to the rate of interest would be lost. In some cases (e.g. Mun)
the object of enhancing the power of the State led them, nevertheless, to
advocate the accumulation of state treasure. But others frankly opposed this
policy:
Schrötter, for instance, employed the usual mercantilist arguments in
drawing a lurid picture of how the circulation in the country would be robbed
of all its money through a greatly increasing state treasury. . .he,
too, drew a perfectly logical parallel between the accumulation of treasure by
the [p.345] monasteries and the export surplus of precious metals,
which, to him, was indeed the worst possible thing which he could think of. Davenant
explained the extreme poverty of many Eastern nations¾who
were believed to have more gold and silver than any other countries in the
world¾by the fact that treasure "is suffered to
stagnate in the Princes' Coffers". . .If hoarding by the state was
considered, at best, a doubtful boon, and often a great danger, it goes
without saying that private hoarding was to be shunned like the pest. It was
one of the tendencies against which innumerable mercantilist writers
thundered, and I do not think it would be possible to find a single
dissentient voice.[1]
(2) The mercantilists were aware of the fallacy of cheapness and
the danger that excessive competition may turn the terms of trade against a
country. Thus Malynes
wrote in his Lex Mercatoria (1622): "Strive not to
undersell others to the hurt of the Commonwealth, under colour to increase
trade: for trade doth not increase when commodities are good cheap, because the
cheapness proceedeth of the small request and scarcity of money, which maketh
things cheap: so that the contrary augmenteth trade when there is plenty of
money, and commodities become dearer being in request".[2]
Professor Heckscher sums up as follows this strand in mercantilist thought:
In the course of a century and a half this standpoint was formulated again
and again in this way, that a country with relatively less money than other
countries must "sell cheap and buy dear". . .
Even in the original edition of the Discourse of the Common Weal,
that is in the middle of the 16th century, this attitude was already
manifested. Hales said, in fact, "And
yet if strangers should be content to take but our wares for theirs, what
should let them to advance the price of other things (meaning: among others,
such as we buy from them), though ours were good cheap unto them? And then
shall we be still losers, and they at the winning hand with us, while they
sell dear and yet buy ours good cheap, and consequently enrich [p.346]
themselves and impoverish us. Yet had I rather advance our wares in price, as
they advance theirs, as we now do; though some be losers thereby, and yet not
so many as should be the other way." On this point he had the unqualified
approval of his editor several decades later (1581). In the 17th century, this
attitude recurred again without any fundamental change in significance. Thus, Malynes
believed this unfortunate position to be the result of what he dreaded
above all things, i.e. a foreign under-valuation of the English
exchange. . .The same conception then recurred continually. In his Verbum
Sapienti (written 1665, published 1691), Petty
believed that the violent
efforts to increase the quantity of money could only cease "when we have
certainly more money than any of our Neighbour States (though never so
little), both in Arithmetical and Geometrical proportion". During the period
between the writing and the publication of this work, Coke
declared, "If our
Treasure were more than our Neighbouring Nations, I did not care whether we
had one fifth part of the Treasure we now have" (1675).[1]
(3) The mercantilists were the originals of "the fear of goods"
and the scarcity of money as causes of unemployment which the classicals were to
denounce two centuries later as an absurdity:
One of the earliest instances of the application of the unemployment
argument as a reason for the prohibition of imports is to be found in Florence
in the year 1426. . . .The English legislation on the matter
goes back to at least 1455. . . .An almost contemporary French
decree of 1466, forming the basis of the silk industry of Lyons, later to
become so famous, was less interesting in so far as it was not actually
directed against foreign goods. But it, too, mentioned the possibility of
giving work to tens of thousands of unemployed men and women. It is seen how
very much this argument was in the air at the time. . .
The first great discussion of this matter, as of nearly all social and
economic problems, occurred in England in the middle of the i6th century or
rather earlier, during the reigns of Henry VIII and Edward VI. In this
connection we cannot but mention a series of writings, written apparently at
the latest in the 1530's, two of which at any rate are believed [p.347]
to have been by Clement Armstrong. . .He formulates it, for example,
in the following terms: "By reason of great abundance of strange merchandises
and wares brought yearly into England hath not only caused scarcity of money,
but hath destroyed all handicrafts, whereby great number of common people
should have works to get money to pay for their meat and drink, which of very
necessity must live idly and beg and steal".[1]
The best instance to my knowledge of a typically mercantilist discussion of
a state of affairs of this kind is the debates in the English House of Commons
concerning the scarcity of money, which occurred in 1621, when a serious
depression had set in, particularly in the cloth export. The conditions were
described very clearly by one of the most influential members of parliament,
Sir Edwin Sandys. He stated that the farmer and the artificer had to suffer
almost everywhere, that looms were standing idle for want of money in the
country, and that peasants were forced to repudiate their contracts, "not
(thanks be to God) for want of fruits of the earth, but for want of money".
The situation led to detailed enquiries into where the money could have got
to, the want of which was felt so bitterly. Numerous attacks were directed
against all persons who were supposed to have contributed either to an export
(export surplus) of precious metals, or to their disappearance on account of
corresponding activities within the country.[2]
Mercantilists were conscious that their policy, as Professor Heckscher puts
it, "killed two birds with one stone". "On the one hand the country was rid of
an unwelcome surplus of goods, which was believed to result in unemployment,
while on the other the total stock of money in the country was increased",[3]
with the resulting advantages of a fall in the rate of interest.
It is impossible to study the notions to which the mercantilists were led by
their actual experiences, without perceiving that there has been a chronic
tendency throughout human history for the propensity to save to be stronger than
the inducement to invest. The [p.348] weakness of the inducement to
invest has been at all times the key to the economic problem. To-day the
explanation of the weakness of this inducement may chiefly lie in the extent of
existing accumulations; whereas, formerly, risks and hazards of all kinds may
have played a larger part. But the result is the same. The desire of, the
individual to augment his personal wealth by abstaining from consumption has
usually been stronger than the inducement to the entrepreneur to augment the
national wealth by employing labour on the construction of durable assets.
(4) The mercantilists were under no illusions as to the
nationalistic character of their policies and their tendency to promote war. It
was national advantage and relative strength at which they were
admittedly aiming.[1]
We may criticise them for the apparent indifference with which they accepted
this inevitable consequence of an international monetary system. But
intellectually their realism is much preferable to the confused thinking of
contemporary advocates of an international fixed gold standard and laissez-faire
in international lending, who believe that it is precisely these policies which
will best promote peace.
For in an economy subject to money contracts and customs more or less fixed
over an appreciable period of time, where the quantity of the domestic
circulation and the domestic rate of interest are primarily determined by the
balance of payments, as they were in Great Britain before the war, there is no
orthodox means open to the authorities for countering unemployment at home
except by struggling for an export surplus and [p.349] an import of the
monetary metal at the expense of their neighbours. Never in history was there a
method devised of such efficacy for setting each country's advantage at variance
with its neighbours' as the international gold (or, formerly, silver) standard.
For it made domestic prosperity directly dependent on a competitive pursuit of
markets and a competitive appetite for the precious metals. When by happy
accident the new supplies of gold and silver were comparatively abundant, the
struggle might be somewhat abated. But with the growth of wealth and the
diminishing marginal propensity to consume, it has tended to become increasingly
internecine. The part played by orthodox economists, whose common sense has been
insufficient to check their faulty logic, has been disastrous to the latest act.
For when in their blind struggle for an escape, some countries have thrown off
the obligations which had previously rendered impossible an autonomous rate of
interest, these economists have taught that a restoration of the former shackles
is a necessary first step to a general recovery.
In truth the opposite holds good. It is the policy of an autonomous rate of
interest, unimpeded by international preoccupations, and of a national
investment programme directed to an optimum level of domestic employment which
is twice blessed in the sense that it helps ourselves and our neighbours at the
same time. And it is the simultaneous pursuit of these policies by all countries
together which is capable of restoring economic health and strength
internationally, whether we measure it by the level of domestic employment or by
the volume of international trade.[1] [p.350]
IV
The mercantilists perceived the existence of the problem without being able
to push their analysis to the point of solving it. But the classical
school ignored the problem, as a consequence of introducing into their premisses
conditions which involved its non-existence; with the result of creating a
cleavage between the conclusions of economic theory and those of common sense.
The extraordinary achievement of the classical theory was to overcome the
beliefs of the "natural man" and, at the same time, to be wrong. As Professor
Heckscher expresses it:
If, then, the underlying attitude towards money and the material from which
money was created did not alter in the period between the Crusades and the
18th century, it follows that we are dealing with deep-rooted notions. Perhaps
the same notions have persisted even beyond the 500 years included in that
period, even though not nearly to the same degree as the "fear of goods". With
the exception of the period of laissez-faire, no age has been free from
these ideas. It was only the unique intellectual tenacity of laissez-faire that
for a time overcame the beliefs of the "natural man" on this point.[1]
It required the unqualified faith of doctrinaire laissez-faire to
wipe out the "fear of goods". . .[which] is the most natural
attitude of the "natural man" in a money economy. Free Trade denied the
existence of factors which appeared to be obvious, and was doomed to be
discredited in the eyes of the man in the street as soon as laissez-faire
could no longer hold the minds of men enchained in its ideology.[2]
I remember Bonar Law's mingled rage and perplexity in face of the economists,
because they were denying what was obvious. He was deeply troubled for an
explanation. One recurs to the analogy between [p.351] the sway of the
classical school of economic theory and that of certain religions. For it is a
far greater exercise of the potency of an idea to exorcise the obvious than to
introduce into men's common notions the recondite and the remote.
V
There remains an allied, but distinct, matter where for centuries, indeed for
several millenniums, enlightened opinion held for certain and obvious a doctrine
which the classical school has repudiated as childish, but which deserves
rehabilitation and honour. I mean the doctrine that the rate of interest is not
self-adjusting at a level best suited to the social advantage but constantly
tends to rise too high, so that a wise Government is concerned to curb it by
statute and custom and even by invoking the sanctions of the moral law.
Provisions against usury are amongst the most ancient economic practices of
which we have record. The destruction of the inducement to invest by an
excessive liquidity-preference was the outstanding evil, the prime impediment to
the growth of wealth, in the ancient and medieval worlds. And naturally so,
since certain of the risks and hazards of economic life diminish the marginal
efficiency of capital whilst others serve to increase the preference for
liquidity. In a world, therefore, which no one reckoned to be safe, it was
almost inevitable that the rate of interest, unless it was curbed by every
instrument at the disposal of society, would rise too high to permit of an
adequate inducement to invest.
I was brought up to believe that the attitude of the Medieval Church to the
rate of interest was inherently absurd, and that the subtle discussions aimed at
distinguishing the return on money-loans from the return to active investment
were merely jesuitical attempts to find a practical escape from a foolish
theory. But I [p.352] now read these discussions as an honest
intellectual effort to keep separate what the classical theory has inextricably
confused together, namely, the rate of interest and the marginal efficiency of
capital. For it now seems clear that the disquisitions of the schoolmen were
directed towards the elucidation of a formula which should allow the schedule of
the marginal efficiency of capital to be high, whilst using rule and custom and
the moral law to keep down the rate of interest.
Even Adam Smith was extremely moderate
in his attitude to the usury laws. For lie was well aware that individual
savings may be absorbed either by investment or by debts, and that there is no
security that they will find an outlet in the former. Furthermore, he favoured a
low rate of interest as increasing the chance of savings finding their outlet in
new investment rather than in debts; and for this reason, in a passage for which
he was severely taken to task by Bentham,[1]
he defended a moderate application of the usury laws.[2]
Moreover, Bentham's criticisms were mainly on the ground that Adam Smith's
Scotch caution was too severe on "projectors" and that a maximum rate of
interest would leave too little margin for the reward of legitimate and socially
advisable risks. For Bentham understood by projectors "all such persons,
as, in the pursuit of wealth, or even of any other object, endeavour, by the
assistance of wealth, to strike into any channel of invention. . .upon
all such persons as, in the line of any of their pursuits, aim at anything that
can be called improvement. . .It falls, in short, upon every
application of the human powers, in which ingenuity stands in need of wealth for
its assistance." Of course Bentham is right in protesting against laws which
stand in the way of taking legitimate risks. "A prudent man", Bentham continues,
"will not, in these circumstances, pick out the good projects [p.353] from
the bad, for he will not meddle with projects at all."[1]
It may be doubted, perhaps, whether the above is just what Adam Smith
intended by his term. Or is it that we are hearing in Bentham (though writing in
March 1787 from "Crichoff in White Russia") the voice of nineteenth-century
England speaking to the eighteenth? For nothing short of the exuberance of the
greatest age of the inducement to investment could have made it possible to lose
sight of the theoretical possibility of its insufficiency.
VI
It is convenient to mention at this point the strange, unduly neglected
prophet Silvio Gesell (1862-1930),
whose work contains flashes of deep insight and who only just failed to reach
down to the essence of the matter. In the post-war years his devotees bombarded
me with copies of his works; yet, owing to certain palpable defects in the
argument, I entirely failed to discover their merit. As is often the case with
imperfectly analysed intuitions, their significance only became apparent after I
had reached my own conclusions in my own way. Meanwhile, like other academic
economists, I treated his profoundly original strivings as being no better than
those of a crank. Since few of the readers of this book are likely to be well
acquainted with the significance of Gesell, I will give to him what would be
otherwise a disproportionate space.
Gesell was a successful German[2]
merchant in [p.354] Buenos Aires who was led to the study of monetary
problems by the crisis of the late 'eighties, which was especially violent in
the Argentine, his first work, Die Reformation im Münzwesen als Brücke zum
socialen Staat, being published in Buenos Aires in 1891. His fundamental
ideas on money were published in Buenos Aires in the same year under the title Nervus
rerum, and many books and pamphlets followed until he retired to Switzerland
in 1906 as a man of some means, able to devote the last decades of his life to
the two most delightful occupations open to those who do not have to earn their
living, authorship and experimental farming.
The first section of his standard work was published in 1906 at Les Hauts
Geneveys, Switzerland, under the title Die Verwirklichung des Rechtes auf dem
vollen Arbeitsertrag, and the second section in 1911 at Berlin under
the title Die neue Lehre vom Zins. The two together were published in
Berlin and in Switzerland during the war (1916) and reached a sixth edition
during his lifetime under the title Die natürliche Wirtschaftsordnung durch
Freiland und Freigeld, the English version (translated by Mr. Philip Pye)
being called The Natural Economic Order. In April 1919 Gesell joined the
short-lived Soviet cabinet of Bavaria as their Minister of Finance, being
subsequently tried by court-martial. The last decade of his life was spent in
Berlin and Switzerland and devoted to propaganda. Gesell, drawing to himself the
semi-religious fervour which had formerly centred round Henry George,
became the revered prophet of a cult with many thousand disciples throughout the
world. The first international convention of the Swiss and German Freiland-Freigeld
Bund and similar organisations from many countries was held in Basle in 1923.
Since his death in 1930 much of the peculiar type of fervour which doctrines
such as his are capable of exciting has been diverted to other (in my opinion
less eminent) prophets. Dr. Büchi is the leader of the movement in England, but
[p.355] its literature seems to be distributed from San Antonio, Texas,
its main strength lying to-day in the United States, where Professor Irving Fisher,
alone amongst academic economists, has recognised its significance.
In spite of the prophetic trappings with which his devotees have decorated
him, Gesell's main book is written in cool, scientific language; though it is
suffused throughout by a more passionate, a more emotional devotion to social
justice than some think decent in a scientist. The part which derives from Henry
George,[1] though doubtless an important
source of the movement's strength, is of altogether secondary interest. The
purpose of the book as a whole may be described as the establishment of an
anti-Marxian socialism, a reaction
against laissez-faire built on theoretical foundations totally unlike
those of Marx in being based on a
repudiation instead of on an acceptance of the classical hypotheses, and on an
unfettering of competition instead of its abolition. I believe that the future
will learn more from the spirit of Gesell than from that of Marx. The preface to
The Natural Economic Order will indicate to the reader, if he will refer
to it, the moral quality of Gesell. The answer to Marxism
is, I think, to be found along the lines of this preface.
Gesell's specific contribution to the theory of money and interest is as
follows. In the first place, he distinguishes clearly between the rate of
interest and the marginal efficiency of capital, and he argues that it is the
rate of interest which sets a limit to the rate of growth of real capital. Next,
he points out that the rate of interest is a purely monetary phenomenon and that
the peculiarity of money, from which flows the significance of the money rate of
interest, lies in the fact that its ownership as a means of storing wealth
involves the holder in negligible carrying charges, and that forms of wealth,
such as stocks of commodities [p.356] which do involve carrying charges,
in fact yield a return because of the standard set by money. He cites the
comparative stability of the rate of interest throughout the ages as evidence
that it cannot depend on purely physical characters, inasmuch as the variation
of the latter from one epoch to another must have been incalculably greater than
the observed changes in the rate of interest; i.e. (in my terminology)
the rate of interest, which depends on constant psychological characters, has
remained stable, whilst the widely fluctuating characters, which primarily
determine the schedule of the marginal efficiency of capital, have determined
not the rate of interest but the rate at which the (more or less) given rate of
interest allows the stock of real capital to grow.
But there is a great defect in Gesell's theory. He shows how it is only the
existence of a rate of money interest which allows a yield to be obtained from
lending out stocks of commodities. His dialogue between Robinson Crusoe and a
stranger[1] is a most excellent economic
parable¾as good as anything of the kind that has
been written¾to demonstrate this point. But, having
given the reason why the money-rate of interest unlike most commodity rates of
interest cannot be negative, he altogether overlooks the need of an explanation
why the money-rate of interest is positive, and he fails to explain why the
money-rate of interest is not governed (as the classical school maintains) by
the standard set by the yield on productive capital. This is because the notion
of liquidity-preference had escaped him. He has constructed only half a theory
of the rate of interest.
The incompleteness of his theory is doubtless the explanation of his work
having suffered neglect at the hands of the academic world. Nevertheless he had
carried his theory far enough to lead him to a practical recommendation, which
may carry with it the essence [p.357] of what is needed, though it is not
feasible in the form in which he proposed it. He argues that the growth of real
capital is held back by the money-rate of interest, and that if this brake were
removed the growth of real capital would be, in the modern world, so rapid that
a zero money-rate of interest would probably be justified, not indeed forthwith,
but within a comparatively short period of time. Thus the prime necessity is to
reduce the money-rate of interest, and this, he pointed out, can be effected by
causing money to incur carrying-costs just like other stocks of barren goods.
This led him to the famous prescription of "stamped" money, with which his name
is chiefly associated and which has received the blessing of Professor Irving
Fisher. According to this proposal currency notes (though it would clearly need
to apply as well to some forms at least of bank-money) would only retain their
value by being stamped each month, like an insurance card, with stamps purchased
at a post office. The cost of the stamps could, of course, be fixed at any
appropriate figure. According to my theory it should be roughly equal to the
excess of the money-rate of interest (apart from the stamps) over the marginal
efficiency of capital corresponding to a rate of new investment compatible with
full employment. The actual charge suggested by Gesell was 1 per mil. per week,
equivalent to 5.2 per cent. per annum. This would be too high in existing
conditions, but the correct figure, which would have to be changed from time to
time, could only be reached by trial and error.
The idea behind stamped money is sound. It is, indeed, possible that means
might be found to apply it in practice on a modest scale. But there are many
difficulties which Gesell did not face. In particular, he was unaware that money
was not unique in having a liquidity-premium attached to it, but differed only
in degree from many other articles, deriving its importance from having a greater
liquidity-premium than any [p.358] other article. Thus if currency notes
were to be deprived of their liquidity-premium by the stamping system, a long
series of substitutes would step into their shoes¾bank-money,
debts at call, foreign money, jewellery and the precious metals generally, and
so forth. As I have mentioned above, there have been times when it was probably
the craving for the ownership of land, independently of its yield, which served
to keep up the rate of interest;¾though under
Gesell's system this possibility would have been eliminated by land
nationalisation.
VII
The theories which we have examined above are directed, in substance, to the
constituent of effective demand which depends on the sufficiency of the
inducement to invest. It is no new thing, however, to ascribe the evils of
unemployment to the insufficiency of the other constituent, namely, the
insufficiency of the propensity to consume. But this alternative explanation of
the economic evils of the day¾equally unpopular with
the classical economists¾played a much smaller part
in sixteenth- and seventeenth-century thinking and has only gathered force in
comparatively recent times.
Though complaints of under-consumption were a very subsidiary aspect of
mercantilist thought, Professor Heckscher quotes a number of examples of what he
calls "the deep-rooted belief in the utility of luxury and the evil of thrift.
Thrift, in fact, was regarded as the cause of unemployment, and for two reasons:
in the first place, because real income was believed to diminish by the amount
of money which did not enter into exchange, and secondly, because saving was
believed to withdraw money from circulation."[1]
In 1598 Laffemas (Les Trésors et
richesses pour mettre l'Estat en Splendeur) denounced the objectors to the
use of [p.359] French silks on the ground that all purchasers of French
luxury goods created a livelihood for the poor, whereas the miser caused them to
die in distress".[1] In 1662 Petty
justified "entertainments, magnificent shews, triumphal arches, etc.", on the
ground that their costs flowed back into the pockets of brewers, bakers,
tailors, shoemakers and so forth. Fortrey
justified "excess of apparel". Von Schrötter
(1686) deprecated sumptuary regulations and declared that he would wish that
display in clothing and the like were even greater. Barbon
(1690) wrote that "Prodigality is a vice that is prejudicial to the Man, but not
to trade. . .Covetousness is a Vice, prejudicial both to Man and
Trade."[2] In 1695 Cary argued that if
everybody spent more, all would obtain larger incomes "and might then live more
plentifully".[3]
But it was by Bernard Mandeville's
Fable of the Bees that Barbon's opinion was mainly popularised, a book
convicted as a nuisance by the grand jury of Middlesex in 1723, which stands out
in the history of the moral sciences for its scandalous reputation. Only one man
is recorded as having spoken a good word for it, namely Dr Johnson, who declared
that it did not puzzle him, but "opened his eyes into real life very much". The
nature of the book's wickedness can be best conveyed by Leslie Stephen's summary
in the Dictionary of National Biography:
Mandeville gave great offence by this book, in which a cynical system of
morality was made attractive by ingenious paradoxes. . .His doctrine
that prosperity was increased by expenditure rather than by saving fell in
with many current economic fallacies not yet extinct.[4]
Assuming with the [p.360] ascetics that human desires were essentially
evil and therefore produced "private vices" and assuming with the common view
that wealth was a "public benefit", he easily showed that all civilisation
implied the development of vicious propensities. . .
The text of the Fable of the Bees is an allegorical poem¾"The
Grumbling Hive, or Knaves turned honest", in which is set forth the
appalling plight of a prosperous community in which all the citizens suddenly
take it into their heads to abandon luxurious living, and the State to cut down
armaments, in the interests of Saving:
No Honour now could be content,
To live and owe for what was spent,
Liv'ries in Broker's shops are hung;
They part with Coaches for a song;
Sell stately Horses by whole sets
and Country-Houses to pay debts.
Vain cost is shunn'd as moral Fraud;
They have no Forces kept Abroad;
Laugh at th' Esteem of Foreigners,
And empty Glory got by Wars;
They fight, but for their Country's sake,
When Right or Liberty's at Stake.
The haughty Chloe
Contracts th' expensive Bill of Fare,
And wears her strong Suit a whole Year.
And what is the result?¾
Now mind the glorious Hive, and see
How Honesty and Trade agree:
The Shew is gone, it thins apace;
And looks with quite another Face,
For 'twas not only they that went,
By whom vast sums were yearly spent;
But Multitudes that lived on them,
Were daily forc'd to do the same.
In vain to other Trades they'd fly;
All were o'er-stocked accordingly.
The price of Land and Houses falls;
Mirac'lous Palaces whose Walls, [p.361]
Like those of Thebes, were rais'd by Play,
Are to be let. . .
The Building Trade is quite destroy'd,
Artificers are not employ'd;
No limner for his Art is fam'd,
Stone-cutters, Carvers are not nam'd.
So "The Moral" is:
Bare Virtue can't make Nations live
In Splendour. They that would revive
A Golden Age, must be as free,
For Acorns as for Honesty.
Two extracts from the commentary which follows the allegory will show that
the above was not without a theoretical basis:
As this prudent economy, which some people call Saving, is in private
families the most certain method to increase an estate, so some imagine that,
whether a country be barren or fruitful, the same method if generally pursued
(which they think practicable) will have the same effect upon a whole nation,
and that, for example, the English might be much richer than they are, if they
would be as frugal as some of their neighbours. This, I think, is an error.[1]
On the contrary, Mandeville concludes:
The great art to make a nation happy, and what we call flourishing,
consists in giving everybody an opportunity of being employed; which to
compass, let a Government's first care be to promote as great a variety of
Manufacures, Arts and Handicrafts as human wit can invent; and the second to
encourage Agriculture and Fishery in all their branches, that the whole Earth
may be forccd to exert itself as well as Man. It is from this Policy and not
from the trifling regulations of Lavishness and Frugality that the greatness
and felicity of Nations must be expected; for let the value of Gold and Silver
rise or fall, the enjoyment of all Societies will ever depend upon the Fruits
of the Earth and the Labour of the People; both which joined together are a
more certain, a more inexhaustible [p.362] and a more real Treasure
than the Gold of Brazil or the Silver of Potosi.
No wonder that such wicked sentiments called down the opprobrium of two
centuries of moralists and economists who felt much more virtuous in possession
of their austere doctrine that no sound remedy was discoverable except in the
utmost of thrift and economy both by the individual and by the state. Petty's "entertainments,
magnificent shews, triumphal arches, etc." gave place to the penny-wisdom of
Gladstonian finance and to a state system which "could not afford" hospitals,
open spaces, noble buildings, even the preservation of its ancient monuments,
far less the splendours of music and the drama, all of which were consigned to
the private charity or magnanimity of improvident individuals.
The doctrine did not reappear in respectable circles for another century,
until in the later phase of Malthus the
notion of the insufficiency of effective demand takes a definite place as a
scientific explanation of unemployment. Since I have already dealt with this
somewhat fully in my essay on Malthus,[1]
it will be sufficient if I repeat here one or two characteristic passages which
I have already quoted in my essay:
We see in almost every part of the world vast powers of production which
are not put into action, and I explain this phenomenon by saying that from the
want of a proper distribution of the actual produce adequate motives are not
furnished to continued production. . .I distinctly maintain that an
attempt to accumulate very rapidly, which necessarily implies a considerable
diminution of unproductive consumption, by greatly impairing the usual motives
to production must prematurely check the progress of wealth. . . But
if it be true that an attempt to accumulate very rapidly will occasion such a
division between labour and profits as almost to destroy both the motive and
the power of future accumulation and consequently the power of maintaining [p.363]
and employing an increasing population, must it not be acknowledged that
such an attempt to accumulate, or that saving too much, may be really
prejudicial to a country?[1]
The question is whether this stagnation of capital, and subsequent
stagnation in the demand for labour arising from increased production without
an adequate proportion of unproductive consumption on the part of the
landlords and capitalists, could take place without prejudice to the country,
without occasioning a less degree both of happiness and wealth than would have
occurred if the unproductive consumption of the landlords and capitalists had
been so proportioned to the natural surplus of the society as to have
continued uninterrupted the motives to production, and prevented first an
unnatural demand for labour and then a necessary and sudden diminution of such
demand. But if this be so, how can it be said with truth that parsimony,
though it may be prejudicial to the producers, cannot be prejudicial to the
state; or that an increase of unproductive consumption among landlords and
capitalists may not sometimes be the proper remedy for a state of things in
which the motives to production fail?[2]
Adam Smith has stated that capitals are increased by parsimony, that every
frugal man is a public benefactor, and that the increase of wealth depends
upon the balance of produce above consumption. That these propositions are
true to a great extent is perfectly unquestionable. . .But it is
quite obvious that they are not true to an indefinite extent, and that the
principles of saving, pushed to excess, would destroy the motive to
production. If every person were satisfied with the simplest food, the poorest
clothing, and the meanest houses, it is certain that no other sort of food,
clothing, and lodging would be in existence. . .The two extremes are
obvious; and it follows that there must be some intermediate point, though the
resources of political economy may not be able to ascertain it, where, taking
into consideration both the power to produce and the will to consume, the
encouragement to the increase of wealth is the greatest.[3]
Of all the opinions advanced by able and ingenious men, which I have ever
met with, the opinion of M. Say, which [p.364]
states that, Un produit consommé ou detruit est un débouché fermé (I. i. ch. 15),
appears to me to be the most directly opposed to just theory, and the most
uniformly contradicted by experience. Yet it directly follows from the new
doctrine, that commodities are to be considered only in their relation to each
other,¾not to the consumers. What, I would ask,
would become of the demand for commodities, if all consumption except bread
and water were suspended for the next half-year? What an accumulation of
commodities! Quels debouchés! What a prodigious market would this
event occasion! [1]
Ricardo, however, was stone-deaf to
what Malthus was saying. The last echo of the controversy is to be found in John
Stuart Mill's discussion of his wages-fund
theory,[2] which in his own mind played
a vital part in his rejection of the later phase of Malthus, amidst the
discussions of which he had, of course, been brought up. Mill's successors
rejected his wages-fund theory but overlooked the fact that Mill's refutation of
Malthus depended on it. Their method was to dismiss the problem from the corpus
of economics not by solving it but by not mentioning it. It altogether
disappeared from controversy. Mr Cairncross, searching recently for traces of it
amongst the minor Victorians,[3] has
found even less, perhaps, than might have been expected.[4]
Theories of under-consumption hibernated until the appearance in 1889 of The
Physiology of Industry, by J. A. Hobson
and A. F. Mummery, the first and most significant of many volumes in which
for nearly fifty years Mr. Hobson has flung himself with unflagging, but almost
unavailing, ardour and courage [p.365] against the ranks of orthodoxy.
Though it is so completely forgotten to-day, the publication of this book marks,
in a sense, an epoch in economic thought.[1]
The Physiology of Industry was written in collaboration with A. F.
Mummery. Mr Hobson has told how the book came to be written as follows:[2]
It was not until the middle 'eighties that my economic heterodoxy began to
take shape. Though the Henry George campaign against land values and the early
agitation of various socialist groups against the visible oppression of the
working classes, coupled with the revelations of the two Booths regarding the
poverty of London, made a deep impression on my feelings, they did not destroy
my faith in Political Economy. That came from what may be called an accidental
contact. While teaching at a school in Exeter I came into personal relations
with a business man named Mummery, known then and afterwards as a great
mountaineer who had discovered another way up the Matterhorn and who, in 1895,
was killed in an attempt to climb the famous Himalayan mountain Nanga Parbat.
My intercourse with him, I need hardly say, did not lie on this physical
plane. But he was a mental climber as well, with a natural eye for a path of
his own finding and a sublime disregard of intellectual authority. This man
entangled me in a controversy about excessive saving, which he regarded as
responsible for the under-employment of capital and labour in periods of bad
trade. For a long time I sought to counter his arguments by the use of the
orthodox economic weapons. But at length he convinced me and I went in with
him to elaborate the over-saving argument in a book entitled The Physiology
of Industry, which was published in 1889. This was the first open step in
my heretical career, and I did not in the least realise its momentous
consequences. For just at that time I had given up my scholastic post and was
opening a new line of work as University Extension Lecturer in Economics and
Literature. The first shock came in a refusal of the London Extension Board to
allow me to [p.366] offer courses of Political Economy. This was due, I
learned, to the intervention of an Economic Professor who had read my book and
considered it as equivalent in rationality to an attempt to prove the flatness
of the earth. How could there be any limit to the amount of useful saving when
every item of saving went to increase the capital structure and the fund for
paying wages? Sound economists could not fail to view with horror an argument
which sought to check the source of all industrial progress.[1]
Another interesting personal experience helped to bring home to me the sense
of my iniquity. Though prevented from lecturing on economics in London, I had
been allowed by the greater liberality of the Oxford University Extension
Movement to address audiences in the Provinces, confining myself to practical
issues relating to working-class life. Now it happened at this time that the
Charity Organisation Society was planning a lecture campaign upon economic
subjects and invited me to prepare a course. I had expressed my willingness to
undertake this new lecture work, when suddenly, without explanation, the
invitation was withdrawn. Even then I hardly realised that in appearing to
question the virtue of unlimited thrift I had committed the unpardonable sin.
In this early work Mr. Hobson with his collaborator expressed himself with
more direct reference to the classical economics (in which he had been brought
up) than in his later writings; and for this reason, as well as because it is
the first expression of his theory, I will quote from it to show how significant
and well-founded were the authors' criticisms and intuitions. They point out in
their preface as follows the nature of the conclusions which they attack:
Saving enriches and spending impoverishes the community along with the
individual, and it may be generally defined as an assertion that the effective
love of money is the root of all economic good. Not merely does it enrich the
thrifty [p.367] individual himself, but it raises wages, gives work to
the unemployed, and scatters blessings on every side. From the daily papers to
the latest economic treatise, from the pulpit to the House of Commons, this
conclusion is reiterated and re-stated till it appears positively impious to
question it. Yet the educated world, supported by the majority of economic
thinkers, up to the publication of Ricardo's work strenuously denied this
doctrine, and its ultimate acceptance was exclusively due to their inability
to meet the now exploded wages-fund doctrine. That the conclusion should have
survived the argument on which it logically stood, can be explained on no
other hypothesis than the commanding authority of the great men who asserted
it. Economic critics have ventured to attack the theory in detail, but they
have shrunk appalled from touching its main conclusions. Our purpose is to
show that these conclusions are not tenable, that an undue exercise of the
habit of saving is possible, and that such undue exercise impoverishes the
Community, throws labourers out of work, drives down wages, and spreads that
gloom and prostration through the commercial world which is known as
Depression in Trade. . .
The object of production is to provide "utilities and conveniences" for
consumers, and the process is a continuous one from the first handling of the
raw material to the moment when it is finally consumed as a utility or a
convenience. The only use of Capital being to aid the production of these
utilities and conveniences, the total used will necessarily vary with the
total of utilities and conveniences daily or weekly consumed. Now saving,
while it increases the existing aggregate of Capital, simultaneously reduces
the quantity of utilities and conveniences consumed; any undue exercise of
this habit must, therefore, cause an accumulation of Capital in excess of that
which is required for use, and this excess will exist in the form of general
over-production.[1]
In the last sentence of this passage there appears the root of Hobson's
mistake, namely, his supposing that it is a ease of excessive saving causing the
actual accumulation of capital in excess of what is required, which is,
in fact, a secondary evil which only occurs through mistakes of foresight;
whereas the primary [p.368] evil is a propensity to save in conditions of
full employment more than the equivalent of the capital which is required, thus
preventing full employment except when there is a mistake of foresight. A page
or two later, however, he puts one half of the matter, as it seems to me, with
absolute precision, though still overlooking the possible rôle of changes in
the rate of interest and in the state of business confidence, factors which he
presumably takes as given:
We are thus brought to the conclusion that the basis on which all economic
teaching since Adam Smith has stood, viz. that the quantity annually produced
is determined by the aggregates of Natural Agents, Capital, and Labour
available, is erroneous, and that, on the contrary, the quantity produced,
while it can never exceed the limits imposed by these aggregates, may be, and
actually is, reduced far below this maximum by the check that undue saving and
the consequent accumulation of over-supply exerts on production; i.e.
that in the normal state of modern industrial Communities, consumption limits
production and not production consumption.[1]
Finally he notices the bearing of his theory on the validity of the orthodox
Free Trade arguments:
We also note that the charge of commercial imbecility, so freely launched
by orthodox economists against our American cousins and other Protectionist
Communities, can no longer be maintained by any of the Free Trade arguments
hitherto adduced, since all these are based on the assumption that over-supply
is impossible.[2]
The subsequent argument is, admittedly, incomplete. But it is the first
explicit statement of the fact that capital is brought into existence not by the
propensity to save but in response to the demand resulting from actual and
prospective consumption. The following portmanteau quotation indicates the line
of thought:
It should be clear that the capital of a community cannot be advantageously
increased without a subsequent increase [p.369] in consumption of
commodities. . .Every increase an saving and in capital requires, in
order to be effectual, a corresponding increase in immediately future
consumption [1]. . .And
when we say future consumption, we do not refer to a future of ten, twenty, or
fifty years hence, but to a future that is but little removed from the
present. . .If increased thrift or caution induces people to save
more in the present, they must consent to consume more in the future [2]. . .No
more capital can economically exist at any point in the productive process
than is required to furnish commodities for the current rate of consumption [3]. . .It
is clear that my thrift in no wise affects the total economic thrift of the
community, but only determines whether a particular portion of the total
thrift shall have been exercised by myself or by somebody else. We shall show
how the thrift of one part of the community has power to force another part to
live beyond their income. [4]. . .Most
modern economists deny that consumption could by any possibility be
insufficient. Can we find any economic force at work which might incite a
community to this excess, and if there be any such forces are there not
efficient checks provided by the mechanism of commerce? It will be shown,
firstly, that in every highly organised industrial society there is constantly
at work a force which naturally operates to induce excess of thrift; secondly,
that the checks alleged to be provided by the mechanism of commerce are either
wholly inoperative or are inadequate to prevent grave commercial evil [5]. . .
The brief answer which Ricardo gave
to the contentions of Malthus and Chalmers
seems to have been accepted as sufficient by most later economists. "Productions
are always bought by productions or services; money is only the medium by
which the exchange is effected. Hence the increased production being always
accompanied by a correspondingly increased ability to get and consume, there
is no possibility of Over-production" (Ricardo, Prin.
of Pol. Econ.
p. 362).[6]
Hobson and Mummery were aware that interest was nothing whatever except
payment for the use of money.[7] They
also knew well enough that their opponents would claim that there would be "such
a fall [p.370] in the rate of interest (or profit) as will act as a check
upon Saving, and restore the proper relation between production and consumption".[1]
They point out in reply that "if a fall of Profit is to induce people to save
less, it must operate in one of two ways, either by inducing them to spend more
or by inducing them to produce less".[2]
As regards the former they argue that when profits fall the aggregate income of
the community is reduced, and "we cannot suppose that when the average rate of
incomes is falling, individuals will be induced to increase their rate of
consumption by the fact that the premium upon thrift is correspondingly
diminished"; whilst as for the second alternative, "it is so far from being our
intention to deny that a fall of profit, due to over-supply, will check
production, that the admission of the operation of this check forms the very
centre of our argument".[3]
Nevertheless, their theory failed of completeness, essentially on account of
their having no independent theory of the rate of interest; with the result that
Mr. Hobson laid too much emphasis (especially in his later books) on
under-consumption leading to over-investment, in the sense of unprofitable
investment, instead of explaining that a relatively weak propensity to consume
helps to cause unemployment by requiring and not receiving the
accompaniment of a compensating volume of new investment, which, even if it may
sometimes occur temporarily through errors of optimism, is in general prevented
from happening at all by the prospective profit falling below the standard set
by the rate of interest.
Since the war there has been a spate of heretical theories of
under-consumption, of which those of Major Douglas are the most famous. The
strength of Major Douglas's advocacy has, of course, largely depended on
orthodoxy having no valid reply to much [p.371] of his destructive
criticism. On the other hand, the detail of his diagnosis, in particular the
so-called A + B theorem, includes much mere
mystification. If Major Douglas had limited his B-items to the financial
provisions made by entrepreneurs to which no current expenditure on replacements
and renewals corresponds, he would be nearer the truth. But even in that case it
is necessary to allow for the possibility of these provisions being offset by
new investment in other directions as well as by increased expenditure on
consumption. Major Douglas is entitled to claim, as against some of his orthodox
adversaries, that he at least has not been wholly oblivious of the outstanding
problem of our economic system. Yet he has scarcely established an equal claim
to rank¾a private, perhaps, but not a major in the
brave army of heretics¾with Mandeville, Malthus,
Gesell and Hobson, who, following their intuitions, have preferred to see the
truth obscurely and imperfectly rather than to maintain error, reached indeed
with clearness and consistency and by easy logic but on hypotheses inappropriate
to the facts.
Footnotes: [p.334] 1 - Vide
his Industry and Trade,
Appendix D; Money, Credit and Commerce, p.130; and Principles
of Economics, Appendix I. [back to text]
[p.334] 2 - His
view of them is well summed up in a footnote to the first edition of his Principles,
p.51: "Much study has been given both in England and Germany to medieval
opinions as to the relation of money to national wealth. On the whole they
are to be regarded as confused through want of a clear understanding of the
functions of money, rather than as wrong in consequence of a deliberate
assumption that the increase in the net wealth of a nation can be effected only
by an increase of the stores of the precious metals in her." [back
to text]
[p.334] 3 - The Nation and the
Athenaeum, November 24, 1923. [back to text]
[p.339] 1 - The remedy of an elastic
wage-unit, so that a depression is met by a reduction in wages, is liable, for
the same reason, to be a means of benefiting ourselves at the expense of our
neighbours. [back to text]
[p.340] 1 - Experience since the age
of Solon at least, and probably, if we had the statistics, for many centuries
before that, indicates what a knowledge of human nature would lead us to expect,
namely, that there is a steady tendency for the wage-unit to rise over long
periods of time and that it can be reduced only amidst the decay and dissolution
economic society. Thus, apart altogether from progress and increasing
population, a gradually increasing stock of money has proved
imperative. [back to text]
[p.341] 1 - They are the more
suitable for my purpose because Prof. Heckscher
is himself an adherent, on the whole, of the classical
theory and much less sympathetic to the mercantilist
theories than I am. Thus there is no risk that his choice of quotations
has been biassed in any way by a desire to illustrate their wisdom. [back
to text]
[p.342] 1 - Heckscher,
Mercantilism, vol. ii. pp. 200, 201, very slightly abridged. [back
to text]
[p.342] 2 - Some
Consideration of the Consequences of the Lowering of Interest and Raising the
Value of Money, 1692, but written some years previously. [back
to text]
[p.343] 1 - He
adds: "not barely on the quantity of money but the quickness of its
circulation". [back to text]
[p.343] 2 - "Use" being, of
course, old-fashioned English for "interest". [back
to text]
[p.343] 3 - Hume
a little later had a foot and a half in the classical
world. For Hume began the practice amongst economists of stressing the
importance of the equilibrium position as compared with the ever-shifting
transition towards it, though he was still enough of a mercantilist
not to overlook the fact that it is in the transition that we actually have our
being: "It is only in this interval or intermediate situation, between the
acquisition of money and a rise of prices, that the increasing quantity of gold
and silver is favourable to industry. ... It is of no manner of consequence,
with regard to the domestic happiness of a state, whether money be in a greater
of less quantity. The good policy of the magistrate consists only in
keeping it, if possible, still increasing; because by that means he keeps alive
a spirit of industry in the nation, and increases the state of labour in which
consists all real power and riches. A nation, whose money decreases, is
actually, at that time, weaker and more miserable than another nation, which
possesses no more money but is on the increasing trend." (Essay On
Money, 1752.) [back to text]
[p.344] 1 - It illustrates the
completeness with which the mercantilist
view, that interest means interest on money (the view which is, as it now
seems to me, indubitably correct), has dropt out, that Prof. Heckscher,
as a good classical economist, sums up
his account of Locke's theory with the
comment ¾ "Locke's argument would be
irrefutable ... if interest really were synonymous with the price for the loan
of money; as this is not so, it is entirely irrelevant" (op. cit.,
vol. ii. p.204). [back to text]
[p.345] 1 - Heckscher,
op. cit. vol. ii. pp.210, 211. [back to text]
[p.345] 2 - Heckscher,
op. cit. vol. ii. p.228. [back to text]
[p.346] 1 - Heckscher,
op. cit. vol. ii. p.235. [back to text]
[p.347] 1 - Heckscher,
op. cit. vol. ii. p.122. [back to text]
[p.347] 2 - Heckscher,
op. cit. vol. ii. p.223. [back to text]
[p.347] 3 - Heckscher,
op. cit. vol. ii. p.178. [back to text]
[p.348] 1 - "Within
the state, mercantilism pursued thoroughgoing dynamic ends. But the
important thing is that this was bound up with a static conception of the total
economic resources in the world; for this it was that created that fundamental
disharmony which sustained the endless commercial wars ... This was the tragedy
of mercantilism. Both the Middle Ages with their universal static ideal
and laissez-faire with its universal dynamic ideal avoided this
consequence" (Heckscher, op.
cit. vol. ii. p.25, 26). [back to text]
[p.349] 1 - The consistent
appreciation of this truth by the International Labour Office, first under
Albert Thomas and subsequently under Mr. H.B. Butler, has stood out
conspicuously amongst the pronouncements of the numerous post-war international
bodies. [back to text]
[p.350] 1 - Heckscher,
op. cit. vol. ii. pp.176-7. [back to text]
[p.350] 2 - Op. cit. vol. ii.
p335. [back to text]
[p.352] 1 - In his
Letter to Adam Smith, appended to his Defence
of Usury. [back to text]
[p.352] 2 - Wealth
of Nations, Book II, chap. 4. [back to text]
[p.353] 1 - Having started to
quote Bentham in this context, I must
remind the reader of his finest passage: "The career of art, the great road
which receives the footsteps of projectors, may be considered as a vast, and
perhaps unbounded, plain, bestrewed with gulphs, such as Curtius was swallowed
up in. Each requires a human victim to fall into it ere it can close, but
when it once closes, it closes to open no more, and so much the path is safe to
those who follow." [back to text]
[p.353] 2 - Born near the Luxemburg
frontier of a German father and a French mother. [back to
text]
[p.355] 1 - Gesell
differed from George in recommending the
payment of compensation when the land is nationalised. [back
to text]
[p.356] 1 - The Natural
Economic Order, pp.297 et seq. [HET]
[back to text] [p.358] 1
- Heckscher, op. cit.
vol. ii. p.208. [back to text]
[p.359] 1 - Op. cit. vol.
ii. p.290. [back to text]
[p.359] 2 - Op. cit. vol.
ii. p.291. [back to text]
[p.359] 3 - Op. cit. vol.
ii. p.209. [back to text]
[p.359] 4 - In his History of
English Thought in the Eighteenth Century Stephen wrote (p.297) in speaking
of "the fallacy made celebrated by Mandeville" that "the complete
confutation of it lies in the doctrine ¾ so rarely
understood that its complete apprehension is, perhaps, the best test of an
economist ¾ the demand for commodities is not demand
for labour." [back to text]
[p.361] 1 - Compare Adam Smith,
the forerunner of the classical
school, who wrote, "What is prudence in the conduct of every private family
can scarce be folly in that of a great Kingdom" ¾
probably with reference to the above passage from Mandeville.
[back to text]
[p.362] 1 - Essays in Biography,
pp.139-47.[back to text]
[p.363] 1 - A letter from Malthus
to Ricardo, dated July 7, 1821.[back
to text]
[p.363] 2 - A letter from Malthus
to Ricardo, dated July 16, 1821.[back
to text]
[p.363] 3 - Preface to Malthus's
Principles of Political Economy, pp.8, 9.[back to
text]
[p.364] 1 - Malthus's
Principles of Political Economy, pp.363, footnote.[back
to text]
[p.364] 2 - J.S. Mill
Political
Economy, Book I. chapter v. There is a most important and
penetrating discussion of this aspect of Mill's theory in Mummery and Hobson's
Physiology of Industry, pp.38 et seq., and, in particular, of his
doctrine (which Marshall, in his very
unsatisfactory discussion of the Wages-Fund Theory, endeavoured to explain away)
that "a demand for commodities is not a demand for labour". [back
to text]
[p.364] 3 - "The Victorians
and Investment", Economic History, 1936 [back
to text]
[p.364] 4 - Fullarton's
tract On the Regulation of Currencies (1844) is the most interesting of
his references. [back to text]
[p.365] 1 - J. M. Robertson's The
Fallacy of Saving, published in 1892, supported the heresy of Mummery and Hobson.
But is is not a book of much value or significance, being entirely lacking in
the penetrating intuitions of The Physiology of Industry. [back
to text]
[p.365] 2 - In an address called
"Confessions of an Economic Heretic", delivered before the London
Ethical Society at Conway Hall on Sunday, July 14, 1935. I reproduce it
here by Mr. Hobson's permission. [back
to text]
[p.366] 1 - Hobson
had written disrespectfully in The Physiology of Industry, p.26:
"Thrift is the source of national wealth, and the more thrifty a nation is
the more wealthy it becomes. Such is the common teaching of almost all
economists; many of them assume a tone of ethical dignity as they plead the
infinite value of thrift; this note alone in all their dreary song has caught
the favour of the public ear." [back to text]
[p.367] 1 - Hobson
and Mummery, Physiology of Industry, pp.iii-v. [back
to text]
[p.368] 1 - Hobson
and Mummery, Physiology of Industry, p.vi. [back
to text]
[p.368] 2 - Op. cit. p.ix.
[back to text]
[p.369] 1 - Op. cit. p.27.
[back to text]
[p.369] 2 - Op. cit. pp.50,
51. [back to text]
[p.369] 3 - Op. cit. p.69.
[back to text]
[p.369] 4 - Op. cit. p.113.
[back to text]
[p.369] 5 - Op. cit. p.100.
[back to text]
[p.369] 6 - Op. cit. p.101.
[back to text]
[p.369] 7 - Op. cit. p.79.
[back to text]
[p.370] 1 - Op. cit. p.117.
[back to text]
[p.370] 2 - Op. cit. p.130.
[back to text]
[p.370] 3 - Hobson
and Mummery, Physiology of Industry, p.131. [back
to text]
|