[p.210]
Chapter 16
SUNDRY OBSERVATIONS ON THE NATURE OF CAPITAL
I
An act of individual saving means¾so to speak¾a
decision not to have dinner to-day. But it does not necessitate a
decision to have dinner or to buy a pair of boots a week hence or a year hence
or to consume any specified thing at any specified date. Thus it depresses the
business of preparing to-day's dinner without stimulating the business of making
ready for some future act of consumption. It is not a substitution of future
consumption-demand for present consumption-demand,¾it
is a net diminution of such demand. Moreover, the expectation of future
consumption is so largely based on current experience of present consumption
that a reduction in the latter is likely to depress the former, with the result
that the act of saving will not merely depress the price of consumption-goods
and leave the marginal efficiency of existing capital unaffected, but may
actually tend to depress the latter also. In this event it may reduce present
investment-demand as well as present consumption-demand.
If saving consisted not merely in abstaining from present consumption but in
placing simultaneously a specific order for future consumption, the effect might
indeed be different. For in that case the expectation of some future yield from
investment would be improved, and the resources released from preparing for
present [p.211] consumption could be turned over to preparing for the
future consumption. Not that they necessarily would be, even in this case, on a
scale equal to the amount of resources released; since the desired
interval of delay might require a method of production so inconveniently "roundabout"
as to have an efficiency well below the current rate of interest, with the
result that the favourable effect on employment of the forward order for
consumption would eventuate not at once but at some subsequent date, so that the
immediate effect of the saving would still be adverse to employment. In
any case, however, an individual decision to save does not, in actual fact,
involve the placing of any specific forward order for consumption, but merely
the cancellation of a present order. Thus, since the expectation of consumption
is the only raison d'être of employment, there should be nothing
paradoxical in the conclusion that a diminished propensity to consume has cet.
par. a depressing effect on employment.
The trouble arises, therefore, because the act of saving implies, not a
substitution for present consumption of some specific additional consumption
which requires for its preparation just as much immediate economic activity as
would have been required by present consumption equal in value to the sum saved,
but a desire for "wealth" as such, that is for a potentiality of consuming an
unspecified article at an unspecified time. The absurd, though almost universal,
idea that an act of individual saving is just as good for effective demand as an
act of individual consumption, has been fostered by the fallacy, much more
specious than the conclusion derived from it, that an increased desire to hold
wealth, being much the same thing as an increased desire to hold investments,
must, by increasing the demand for investments, provide a stimulus to their
production; so that current investment is promoted by individual saving to the
same extent as present consumption is diminished. [p.212]
It is of this fallacy that it is most difficult to disabuse men's minds. It
comes from believing that the owner of wealth desires a capital-asset as such,
whereas what he really desires is its prospective yield. Now, prospective
yield wholly depends on the expectation of future effective demand in relation
to future conditions of supply. If, therefore, an act of saving does nothing to
improve prospective yield, it does nothing to stimulate investment. Moreover, in
order that [RES] an individual saver may attain his desired goal of the
ownership of wealth, it is not necessary that a new capital-asset should
be produced wherewith to satisfy him. The mere act of saving by one individual,
being two-sided as we have shown above, forces some other individual to
transfer to him some article of wealth old or new. Every act of saving involves
a "forced" inevitable transfer of wealth to him who saves, though he in his turn
may suffer from the saving of others. These transfers of wealth do not require
the creation of new wealth¾indeed, as we have seen,
they may be actively inimical to it. The creation of new wealth wholly depends
on the prospective yield of the new wealth reaching the standard set by the
current rate of interest. The prospective yield of the marginal new investment
is not increased by the fact that someone wishes to increase his wealth, since
the prospective yield of the marginal new investment depends on the expectation
of a demand for a specific article at a specific date.
Nor do we avoid this conclusion by arguing that what the owner of wealth
desires is not a given prospective yield but the best available prospective
yield, so that an increased desire to own wealth reduces the prospective yield
with which the producers of new investment have to be content. For this
overlooks the fact that there is always an alternative to the ownership of real
capital-assets, namely the ownership of money and debts; so that the prospective
yield with which [p.213] the producers of new investment have to be
content cannot fall below the standard set by the current rate of interest. And
the current rate of interest depends, as we have seen, not on the strength of
the desire to hold wealth, but on the strengths of the desires to hold it in
liquid and in illiquid forms respectively, coupled with the amount of the supply
of wealth in the one form relatively to the supply of it in the other. If the
reader still finds himself perplexed, let him ask himself why, the quantity of
money being unchanged, a fresh act of saving should diminish the sum which it is
desired to keep in liquid form at the existing rate of interest.
Certain deeper perplexities, which may arise when we try to probe still
further into the whys and wherefores, will be considered in the next
chapter.
II
It is much preferable to speak of capital as having a yield over the course
of its life in excess of its original cost, than as being productive. For
the only reason why an asset offers a prospect of yielding during its life
services having an aggregate value greater than its initial supply price is
because it is scarce; and it is kept scarce because of the competition of
the rate of interest on money. If capital becomes less scarce, the excess yield
will diminish, without its having become less productive¾at
least in the physical sense.
I sympathise, therefore, with the pre-classical doctrine that everything is produced
by labour, aided by what used to be called art and is now called technique,
by natural resources which are free or cost a rent according to their scarcity
or abundance, and by the results of past labour, embodied in assets, which also
command a price according to their scarcity or abundance. It is preferable to
regard labour, including, of course, the personal services of the entrepreneur
and his assistants, [p.214] as the sole factor of production, operating
in a given environment of technique, natural resources, capital equipment and
effective demand. This partly explains why we have been able to take the unit of
labour as the sole physical unit which we require in our economic system, apart
from units of money and of time.
It is true that some lengthy or roundabout processes are physically
efficient. But so are some short processes. Lengthy processes are not physically
efficient because they are long. Some, probably most, lengthy processes would be
physically very inefficient, for there are such things as spoiling or wasting
with time.[1] With a given labour force
there is a definite limit to the quantity of labour embodied in roundabout
processes which can be used to advantage. Apart from other considerations, there
must be a due proportion between the amount of labour employed in making
machines and the amount which will be employed in using them. The ultimate
quantity of value will not increase indefinitely, relatively to the
quantity of labour employed, as the processes adopted become more and more
roundabout, even if their physical efficiency is still increasing. Only if the
desire to postpone consumption were strong enough to produce a situation in
which full employment required a volume of investment so great as to involve a
negative marginal efficiency of capital, would a process become advantageous
merely because it was lengthy; in which event we should employ physically inefficient
processes, provided they were sufficiently lengthy for the gain from
postponement to outweigh their inefficiency. We should in fact have a situation
in which short processes would have to be kept sufficiently scarce for
their physical efficiency to outweigh the disadvantage of the early delivery of
their product. A correct theory, therefore, must be reversible so as to be able
to cover the eases of the marginal efficiency of capital corresponding [p.215]
either to a positive or to a negative rate of interest; and it is, I think, only
the scarcity theory outlined above which is capable of this.
Moreover there are all sorts of reasons why various kinds of services and
facilities are scarce and therefore expensive relatively to the quantity of
labour involved. For example, smelly processes command a higher reward, because
people will not undertake them otherwise. So do risky processes. But we do not
devise a productivity theory of smelly or risky processes as such. In short, not
all labour is accomplished in equally agreeable attendant circumstances; and
conditions of equilibrium require that articles produced in less agreeable
attendant circumstances (characterised by smelliness, risk or the lapse of time)
must be kept sufficiently scarce to command a higher price. But if the lapse of
time becomes an agreeable attendant circumstance, which is a quite possible case
and already holds for many individuals, then, as I have said above, it is the
short processes which must be kept sufficiently scarce.
Given the optimum amount of roundaboutness, we shall, of course, select the
most efficient roundabout processes which we can find up to the required
aggregate. But the optimum amount itself should be such as to provide at the
appropriate dates for that part of consumers' demand which it is desired to
defer. In optimum conditions, that is to say, production should be so organised
as to produce in the most efficient manner compatible with delivery at the dates
at which consumers' demand is expected to become effective. It is no use to
produce for delivery at a different date from this, even though the physical
output could be increased by changing the date of delivery;¾except
in so far as the prospect of a larger meal, so to speak, induces the consumer to
anticipate or postpone the hour of dinner. If, after hearing full particulars of
the meals he can get by fixing dinner at [p.216] different hours, the
consumer is expected to decide in favour of 8 o'clock, it is the business of the
cook to provide the best dinner he can for service at that hour, irrespective of
whether 7.30, 8 o'clock or 8.30 is the hour which would suit him best if time
counted for nothing, one way or the other, and his only task was to produce the
absolutely best dinner. In some phases of society it may be that we could get
physically better dinners by dining later than we do; but it is equally
conceivable in other phases that we could get better dinners by dining earlier.
Our theory must, as I have said above, be applicable to both contingencies.
If the rate of interest were zero, there would be an optimum interval for any
given article between the average date of input and the date of consumption, for
which labour cost would be a minimum;¾a shorter
process of production would be less efficient technically, whilst a longer
process would also be less efficient by reason of storage costs and
deterioration. If, however, the rate of interest exceeds zero, a new element of
cost is introduced which increases with the length of the process, so that the
optimum interval will be shortened, and the current input to provide for the
eventual delivery of the article will have to be curtailed until the prospective
price has increased sufficiently to cover the increased cost¾a
cost which will be increased both by the interest charges and also by the
diminished efficiency of the shorter method of production. Whilst if the rate of
interest falls below zero (assuming this to be technically possible), the
opposite is the case. Given the prospective consumers' demand, current input
to-day has to compete, so to speak, with the alternative of starting input at a
later date; and, consequently, current input will only be worth while when the
greater cheapness, by reason of greater technical efficiency or prospective
price changes, of producing later on rather than now, is insufficient to offset
the smaller return from negative [p.217] interest. In the case of the
great majority of articles it would involve great technical inefficiency
to start up their input more than a very modest length of time ahead of their
prospective consumption. Thus even if the rate of interest is zero, there is a
strict limit to the proportion of prospective consumers' demand which it is
profitable to begin providing for in advance; and, as the rate of interest
rises, the proportion of the prospective consumers' demand for which it pays to
produce to-day shrinks pari passu.
III
We have seen that capital has to be kept scarce enough in the long-period to
have a marginal efficiency which is at least equal to the rate of interest for a
period equal to the life of the capital, as determined by psychological and
institutional conditions. What would this involve for a society which finds
itself so well equipped with capital that its marginal efficiency is zero and
would be negative with any additional investment; yet possessing a monetary
system, such that money will "keep" and involves negligible costs of storage and
safe custody, with the result that in practice interest cannot be negative; and,
in conditions of full employment, disposed to save?
If, in such circumstances, we start from a position of full employment,
entrepreneurs will necessarily make losses if they continue to offer employment
on a scale which will utilise the whole of the existing stock of capital. Hence
the stock of capital and the level of employment will have to shrink until the
community becomes so impoverished that the aggregate of saving has become zero,
the positive saving of some individuals or groups being offset by the negative
saving of others. Thus for a society such as we have supposed, the position of
equilibrium, under conditions of laissez-faire, will be one in which
employment is low enough [p.218] and the standard of life sufficiently
miserable to bring savings to zero. More probably there will be a cyclical
movement round this equilibrium position. For if there is still room for
uncertainty about the future, the marginal efficiency of capital will
occasionally rise above zero leading to a "boom", and in the succeeding "slump"
the stock of capital may fall for a time below the level which will yield a
marginal efficiency of zero in the long run. Assuming correct foresight, the
equilibrium stock of capital which will have a marginal efficiency of precisely
zero will, of course, be a smaller stock than would correspond to full
employment of the available labour; for it will be the equipment which
corresponds to that proportion of unemployment which ensures zero saving.
The only alternative position of equilibrium would be given by a situation in
which a stock of capital sufficiently great to have a marginal efficiency of
zero also represents an amount of wealth sufficiently great to satiate to the
full the aggregate desire on the part of the public to make provision for the
future, even with full employment, in circumstances where no bonus is obtainable
in the form of interest. It would, however, be an unlikely coincidence that the
propensity to save in conditions of full employment should become satisfied just
at the point where the stock of capital reaches the level where its marginal
efficiency is zero. If, therefore, this more favourable possibility comes to the
rescue, it will probably take effect, not just at the point where the rate of
interest is vanishing, but at some previous point during the gradual decline of
the rate of interest.
We have assumed so far an institutional factor which prevents the rate of
interest from being negative, in the shape of money which has negligible
carrying costs. In fact, however, institutional and psychological factors are
present which set a limit much above zero to the practicable decline in the rate
of interest. In [p.219] particular the costs of bringing borrowers and
lenders together and uncertainty as to the future of the rate of interest, which
we have examined above, set a lower limit, which in present circumstances may
perhaps be as high as 2 or 2½ per cent on long term. If this should prove
correct, the awkward possibilities of an increasing stock of wealth, in
conditions where the rate of interest can fall no further under laissez-faire,
may soon be realised in actual experience Moreover if the minimum level to which
it is practicable to bring the rate of interest is appreciably above zero, there
is less likelihood of the aggregate desire to accumulate wealth being satiated
before the rate of interest has reached its minimum level.
The post-war experiences of Great Britain and the United States are, indeed,
actual examples of how an accumulation of wealth, so large that its marginal
efficiency has fallen more rapidly than the rate of interest can fall in the
face of the prevailing institutional and psychological factors, can interfere,
in conditions mainly of laissez-faire, with a reasonable level of
employment and with the standard of life which the technical conditions of
production are capable of furnishing.
It follows that of two equal communities, having the same technique but
different stocks of capital, the community with the smaller stocks of capital
may be able for the time being to enjoy a higher standard of life than the
community with the larger stock; though when the poorer community has caught up
the rich¾as, presumably, it eventually will¾then
both alike will suffer the fate of Midas. This disturbing conclusion depends, of
course, on the assumption that the propensity to consume and the rate of
investment are not deliberately controlled in the social interest but are mainly
left to the influences of laissez-faire.
If¾for whatever reason¾the
rate of interest cannot fall as fast as the marginal efficiency of capital would
fall with a rate of accumulation corresponding to what [p.220] the
community would choose to save at a rate of interest equal to the marginal
efficiency of capital in conditions of full employment, then even a diversion of
the desire to hold wealth towards assets, which will in fact yield no economic
fruits whatever, will increase economic well-being. In so far as millionaires
find their satisfaction in building mighty mansions to contain their bodies when
alive and pyramids to shelter them after death, or, repenting of their sins,
erect cathedrals and endow monasteries or foreign missions, the day when
abundance of capital will interfere with abundance of output may be postponed. "To
dig holes in the ground", paid for out of savings, will increase, not only
employment, but the real national dividend of useful goods and services. It is
not reasonable, however, that a sensible community should be content to remain
dependent on such fortuitous and often wasteful mitigations when once we
understand the influences upon which effective demand depends.
IV
Let us assume that steps are taken to ensure that the rate of interest is
consistent with the rate of investment which corresponds to full employment. Let
us assume, further, that State action enters in as a balancing factor to provide
that the growth of capital equipment shall be such as to approach
saturation-point at a rate which does not put a disproportionate burden on the
standard of life of the present generation.
On such assumptions I should guess that a properly run community equipped
with modern technical resources, of which the population is not increasing rapidly,
ought to be able to bring down the marginal efficiency of capital in equilibrium
approximately to zero within a single generation; so that we should attain the
conditions of a quasi-stationary community where change and progress would
result only from [p.221] changes in technique, taste, population and
institutions, with the products of capital selling at a price proportioned to
the labour, etc., embodied in them on just the same principles as govern the
prices of consumption-goods into which capital-charges enter in an insignificant
degree.
If I am right in supposing it to be comparatively easy to make capital-goods
so abundant that the marginal efficiency of capital is zero, this may be the
most sensible way of gradually getting rid of many of the objectionable features
of capitalism. For a little reflection will show what enormous social changes
would result from a gradual disappearance of a rate of return on accumulated
wealth. A man would still be free to accumulate his earned income with a view to
spending it at a later date. But his accumulation would not grow. He would
simply be in the position of Pope's father, who, when he retired from business,
carried a chest of guineas with him to his villa at Twickenham and met his
household expenses from it as required.
Though the rentier would disappear, there would still be room, nevertheless,
for enterprise and skill in the estimation of prospective yields about which
opinions could differ. For the above relates primarily to the pure rate of
interest apart from any allowance for risk and the like, and not to the gross
yield of assets including the return in respect of risk. Thus unless the pure
rate of interest were to be held at a negative figure, there would still be a
positive yield to skilled investment in individual assets having a doubtful
prospective yield. Provided there was some measurable unwillingness to undertake
risk, there would also be a positive net yield from the aggregate of such assets
over a period of time. But it is not unlikely that, in such circumstances, the
eagerness to obtain a yield from doubtful investments might be such that they
would show in the aggregate a negative net yield.
Footnotes: [p.214] 1 - Cf.
Marshall's note on Böhm-Bawerk,
Principles, p.583. [back to text]
|