[p.222]
Chapter 17
THE ESSENTIAL PROPERTIES OF INTEREST AND MONEY
I
It seems, then, that the rate of interest on money plays a peculiar
part in setting a limit to the level of employment, since it sets a standard to
which the marginal efficiency of a capital-asset must attain if it is to be
newly produced. That this should be so, is, at first sight, most perplexing. It
is natural to enquire wherein the peculiarity of money lies as distinct from
other assets, whether it is only money which has a rate of interest, and what
would happen in a non-monetary economy. Until we have answered these questions,
the full significance of our theory will not be clear.
The money-rate of interest¾we may remind the
reader¾is nothing more than the percentage excess of
a sum of money contracted for forward delivery, e.g. a year hence, over
what we may call the "spot" or cash price of the sum thus contracted for forward
delivery. It would seem, therefore, that for every kind of capital-asset there
must be an analogue of the rate of interest on money. For there is a definite
quantity of (e.g.) wheat to be delivered a year hence which has the same
exchange value to-day as 100 quarters of wheat for "spot" delivery. If the
former quantity is 105 quarters, we may say that the wheat-rate of interest is 5
per cent. per annum; and if it is 95 quarters, that it is minus 5 per
cent. per annum. Thus for every durable commodity we have a rate of interest in
terms of itself,¾a [p.223] wheat-rate of
interest, a copper-rate of interest, a house-rate of interest, even a
steel-plant-rate of interest.
The difference between the "future" and "spot" contracts for a commodity,
such as wheat, which are quoted in the market, bears a definite relation to the
wheat-rate of interest, but, since the future contract is quoted in terms of
money for forward delivery and not in terms of wheat for spot delivery, it also
brings in the money-rate of interest. The exact relationship is as follows:
Let us suppose that the spot price of wheat is £100 per 100 quarters, that
the price of the "future" contract for wheat for delivery a year hence is £107
per 100 quarters, and that the money-rate of interest is 5 per cent.; what is
the wheat-rate of interest? £100 spot will buy £105 for forward delivery, and
£105 for forward delivery will buy 105/107 × 100 ( = 98)
quarters for forward delivery. Alternatively £100 spot will buy 100 quarters of
wheat for spot delivery. Thus 100 quarters of wheat for spot delivery will buy
98 quarters for forward delivery. It follows that the wheat-rate of interest is minus
2 per cent., per annum.[1]
It follows from this that there is no reason why their rates of interest
should be the same for different commodities,¾why
the wheat-rate of interest should be equal to the copper-rate of interest. For
the relation between the "spot" and "future" contracts, as quoted in the market,
is notoriously different for different commodities. This, we shall find, will
lead us to the clue we are seeking. For it may be that it is the greatest of
the own-rates of interest (as we may call them) which rules the roost (because
it is the greatest of these rates that the marginal efficiency of a
capital-asset must attain if it is to be newly produced); and that there are
reasons why it is the money-rate of interest which is often the greatest
(because, as we shall find, certain [p.224] forces, which operate
to reduce the own-rates of interest of other assets, do not operate in the case
of money).
It may be added that, just as there are differing commodity-rates of interest
at any time, so also exchange dealers are familiar with the fact that the rate
of interest is not even the same in terms of two different moneys, e.g.
sterling and dollars. For here also the difference between the "spot" and "future"
contracts for a foreign money in terms of sterling are not, as a rule, the same
for different foreign moneys.
Now each of these commodity standards offers us the same facility as money
for measuring the marginal efficiency of capital. For we can take any commodity
we choose, e.g. wheat; calculate the wheat-value of the prospective
yields of any capital asset; and the rate of discount which makes the present
value of this series of wheat annuities equal to the present supply price of the
asset in terms of wheat gives us the marginal efficiency of the asset in terms
of wheat. If no change is expected in the relative value of two alternative
standards, then the marginal efficiency of a capital-asset will be the same in
whichever of the two standards it is measured, since the numerator and
denominator of the fraction which leads up to the marginal efficiency will be
changed in the same proportion. If, however, one of the alternative standards is
expected to change in value in terms of the other, the marginal efficiencies of
capital-assets will be changed by the same percentage, according to which
standard they are measured in. To illustrate this let us take the simplest case
where wheat, one of the alternative standards, is expected to appreciate at a
steady rate of a per cent. per annum in terms of money; the marginal
efficiency of an asset, which is x per cent. in terms of money, will then
be x - a per cent. in terms
of wheat. Since the marginal efficiencies of all capital-assets will be altered
by the same amount, it follows that their order of magnitude will be the same
irrespective of the standard which is selected.[p.225]
If there were some composite commodity which could be regarded strictly
speaking as representative, we could regard the rate of interest and the
marginal efficiency of capital in terms of this commodity as being, in a sense,
uniquely the rate of interest and the marginal efficiency of
capital. But there are, of course, the same obstacles in the way of this as
there are to setting up a unique standard of value.
So far, therefore, the money-rate of interest has no uniqueness compared with
other rates of interest, but is on precisely the same footing. Wherein, then,
lies the peculiarity of the money-rate of interest which gives it the
predominating practical importance attributed to it in the preceding chapters?
Why should the volume of output and employment be more intimately bound up with
the money-rate of interest than with the wheat-rate of interest or the
house-rate of interest?
II
Let us consider what the various commodity-rates of interest over a period of
(say) a year are likely to be for different types of assets. Since we are taking
each commodity in turn as the standard, the returns on each commodity must be
reckoned in this context as being measured in terms of itself.
There are three attributes which different types of assets possess in
different degrees; namely, as follows:
(i) Some assets produce a yield or output q, measured in
terms of themselves, by assisting some process of production or supplying
services to a consumer.
(ii) Most assets, except money, suffer some wastage or involve
some cost through the mere passage of time (apart from any change in their
relative value), irrespective of their being used to produce a yield; i.e.
they involve a carrying cost c measured in terms of themselves. It does
not matter for our present pur-[p.226]pose exactly where we draw the line
between the costs which we deduct before calculating q and those which we
include in c, since in what follows we shall be exclusively concerned
with q - c.
(iii) Finally, the power of disposal over an asset during a period
may offer a potential convenience or security, which is not equal for assets of
different kinds, though the assets themselves are of equal initial value. There
is, so to speak, nothing to show for this at the end of the period in the shape
of output; yet it is something for which people are ready to pay something. The
amount (measured in terms of itself) which they are willing to pay for the
potential convenience or security given by this power of disposal (exclusive of
yield or carrying cost attaching to the asset), we shall call its
liquidity-premium l.
It follows that the total return expected from the ownership of an asset over
a period is equal to its yield minus its carrying cost plus its
liquidity-premium, i.e. to q - c + l.
That is to say, q - c + l
is the own-rate of interest of any commodity, where q, c and l
are measured in terms of itself as the standard.
It is characteristic of instrumental capital (e.g. a machine) or of
consumption capital (e.g. a house) which is in use, that its yield should
normally exceed its carrying cost, whilst its liquidity-premium is probably
negligible; of a stock of liquid goods or of surplus laid-up instrumental or
consumption capital that it should incur a carrying cost in terms of itself
without any yield to set off against it, the liquidity-premium in this case also
being usually negligible as soon as stocks exceed a moderate level, though
capable of being significant in special circumstances; and of money that its
yield is nil and its carrying cost negligible, but its liquidity-premium
substantial. Different commodities may, indeed, have differing degrees of
liquidity-premium amongst themselves, and money may incur some degree of
carrying costs, e.g. for safe [p.227] custody. But it is an
essential difference between money and all (or most) other assets that in the
case of money its liquidity-premium much exceeds its carrying cost, whereas in
the case of other assets their carrying cost much exceeds their
liquidity-premium. Let us, for purposes of illustration, assume that on houses
the yield is q1 and the carrying cost and liquidity-premium
negligible; that on wheat the carrying cost is c2 and the
yield and liquidity-premium negligible; and that on money the liquidity-premium
is l3 and the yield and carrying cost negligible. That is to
say, q1 is the house-rate of interest, - c2
the wheat-rate of interest, and l3 the money-rate of interest.
To determine the relationships between the expected returns on different
types of assets which are consistent with equilibrium, we must also know what
the changes in relative values during the year are expected to be. Taking money
(which need only be a money of account for this purpose, and we could equally
well take wheat) as our standard of measurement, let the expected percentage
appreciation (or depreciation) of houses be a1 and of wheat a2.
q1, - c2 and
l3 we have called the own-rates of interest of houses, wheat
and money in terms of themselves as the standard of value; i.e. q1
is the house-rate of interest in terms of houses, - c2
is the wheat-rate of interest in terms of wheat, and l3 is the
money-rate of interest in terms of money. It will also be useful to call a1 + q1,
a2 - c2
and l3, which stand for the same quantities reduced to money
as the standard of value, the house-rate of money-interest, the wheat-rate of
money-interest and the money-rate of money-interest respectively. With this
notation it is easy to see that the demand of wealth-owners will be directed to
houses, to wheat or to money, according as a1 + q1
or a2 - c2
or l3 is greatest. Thus in equilibrium the demand-prices of
houses and wheat in terms of money will be such that there is nothing to choose
in the way of advantage between the alter-[p.228]natives;¾ i.e. a1 + q1, a2 - c2
and l3 will be equal. The choice of the standard of
value will make no difference to this result because a shift from one standard
to another will change all the terms equally, i.e. by an amount equal to
the expected rate of appreciation (or depreciation) of the new standard in terms
of the old.
Now those assets of which the normal supply-price is less than the
demand-price will be newly produced; and these will be those assets of which the
marginal efficiency would be greater (on the basis of their normal supply-price)
than the rate of interest (both being measured in the same standard of value
whatever it is). As the stock of the assets, which begin by having a marginal
efficiency at least equal to the rate of interest, is increased, their marginal
efficiency (for reasons, sufficiently obvious, already given) tends to fall.
Thus a point will come at which it no longer pays to produce them, unless the
rate of interest falls pari passu. When there is no asset of which
the marginal efficiency reaches the rate of interest, the further production of
capital-assets will come to a standstill.
Let us suppose (as a mere hypothesis at this stage of the argument) that
there is some asset (e.g. money) of which the rate of interest is fixed
(or declines more slowly as output increases than does any other commodity's
rate of interest); how is the position adjusted? Since a1 + q1,
a2 - c2
and l3 are necessarily equal, and since l3
by hypothesis is either fixed or falling more slowly than q1
or - c2, it follows that a1
and a2 must be rising. In other words, the present money-price
of every commodity other than money tends to fall relatively to its expected
future price. Hence, if q1 and - c2
continue to fall, a point comes at which it is not profitable to produce any of
the commodities, unless the cost of production at some future date is expected
to rise above the present cost by an amount which will cover the cost of
carrying a stock produced now to the date of the prospective higher price.[p.229]
It is now apparent that our previous statement to the effect that it is the
money-rate of interest which sets a limit to the rate of output, is not strictly
correct. We should have said that it is that asset's rate of interest which
declines most slowly as the stock of assets in general increases, which
eventually knocks out the profitable production of each of the others,¾except
in the contingency, just mentioned, of a special relationship between the
present and prospective costs of production. As output increases, own-rates of
interest decline to levels at which one asset after another falls below the
standard of profitable production;¾until, finally,
one or more own-rates of interest remain at a level which is above that of the
marginal efficiency of any asset whatever.
If by money we mean the standard of value, it is clear that it is not
necessarily the money-rate of interest which makes the trouble. We could not get
out of our difficulties (as some have supposed) merely by decreeing that wheat
or houses shall be the standard of value instead of gold or sterling. For, it
now appears that the same difficulties will ensue if there continues to exist any
asset of which the own-rate of interest is reluctant to decline as output
increases. It may be, for example, that gold will continue to fill this rôle in
a country which has gone over to an inconvertible paper standard.
III
In attributing, therefore, a peculiar significance to the money-rate of
interest, we have been tacitly assuming that the kind of money to which we are
accustomed has some special characteristics which lead to its own-rate of
interest in terms of itself as standard being more reluctant to fall as the
stock of assets in general [RES] increases than the own-rates of interest
of any other assets in terms of themselves. Is this assumption justified?
Reflection shows, I think, that the following peculiarities, which [p.230] commonly
characterise money as we know it, are capable of justifying it. To the extent
that the established standard of value has these peculiarities, the summary
statement, that it is the money-rate of interest which is the significant rate
of interest, will hold good.
(i) The first characteristic which tends towards the above
conclusion is the fact that money has, both in the long and in the short period,
a zero, or at any rate a very small, elasticity of production, so far as the
power of private enterprise is concerned, as distinct from the monetary
authority;¾elasticity of production[1]
meaning, in this context, the response of the quantity of labour applied to
producing it to a rise in the quantity of labour which a unit of it will
command. Money, that is to say, cannot be readily produced;¾labour
cannot be turned on at will by entrepreneurs to produce money in increasing
quantities as its price rises in terms of the wage-unit. In the case of an
inconvertible managed currency this condition is strictly satisfied. But in the
case of a gold-standard currency it is also approximately so, in the sense that
the maximum proportional addition to the quantity of labour which can be thus
employed is very small, except indeed in a country of which gold-mining is the
major industry.
Now, in the case of assets having an elasticity of production, the reason why
we assumed their own-rate of interest to decline was because we assumed the
stock of them to increase as the result of a higher rate of output. In the case
of money, however¾postponing, for the moment, our
consideration of the effects of reducing the wage-unit or of a deliberate
increase in its supply by the monetary authority¾the
supply is fixed. Thus the characteristic that money cannot be readily produced
by labour gives at once some prima facie presumption for the view that
its own-rate of interest will be relatively reluctant to fall; whereas if money
could be grown like a crop or manufactured [p.231] like a motor-car,
depressions would be avoided or mitigated because, if the price of other assets
was tending to fall in terms of money, more labour would be diverted into the
production of money;¾as we see to be the case in
gold-mining countries, though for the world as a whole the maximum diversion in
this way is almost negligible.
(ii) Obviously, however, the above condition is satisfied, not
only by money, but by all pure rent-factors, the production of which is
completely inelastic. A second condition, therefore, is required to distinguish
money from other rent elements.
The second differentia of money is that it has an elasticity of
substitution equal, or nearly equal, to zero which means that as the exchange
value of money rises there is no tendency to substitute some other factor for
it;¾except, perhaps, to some trifling extent, where
the money-commodity is also used in manufacture or the arts. This follows from
the peculiarity of money that its utility is solely derived from its
exchange-value, so that the two rise and fall pari passu, with the result
that as the exchange value of money rises there is no motive or tendency, as in
the case of rent-factors, to substitute some other factor for it.
Thus, not only is it impossible to turn more labour on to producing money
when its labour-price rises, but money is a bottomless sink for purchasing
power, when the demand for it increases, since there is no value for it at which
demand is diverted¾as in the case of other
rent-factors¾so as to slop over into a demand for
other things.
The only qualification to this arises when the rise in the value of money
leads to uncertainty as to the future maintenance of this rise; in which event, a1
and a2 are increased, which is tantamount to an increase in
the commodity-rates of money-interest and is, therefore, stimulating to the
output of other assets.
(iii) Thirdly, we must consider whether these con-[p.232]clusions
are upset by the fact that, even though the quantity of money cannot be
increased by diverting labour into producing it, nevertheless an assumption that
its effective supply is rigidly fixed would be inaccurate. In particular, a
reduction of the wage-unit will release cash from its other uses for the
satisfaction of the liquidity-motive; whilst, in addition to this, as
money-values fall, the stock of money will bear a higher proportion to the total
wealth of the community.
It is not possible to dispute on purely theoretical grounds that this
reaction might be capable of allowing an adequate decline in the money-rate of
interest. There are, however, several reasons, which taken in combination are of
compelling force, why in an economy of the type to which we are accustomed it is
very probable that the money-rate of interest will often prove reluctant to
decline adequately:
(a) We have to allow, first of all, for the reactions of
a fall in the wage-unit on the marginal efficiencies of other assets in terms of
money;¾for it is the difference between these
and the money-rate of interest with which we are concerned. If the effect of the
fall in the wage-unit is to produce an expectation that it will subsequently
rise again, the result will be wholly favourable. If, on the contrary, the
effect is to produce an expectation of a further fall, the reaction on the
marginal efficiency of capital may offset the decline in the rate of interest. [1]
(b) The fact that wages tend to be sticky in terms of
money, the money-wage being more stable than the real wage, tends to limit the
readiness of the wage-unit to fall in terms of money. Moreover, if this were not
so, the position might be worse rather than better; because, if money-wages were
to fall easily, this might often tend to create an expectation of a further fall
with unfavourable reactions on the marginal efficiency of capital.[p.233]
Furthermore, if wages were to be fixed in terms of some other commodity, e.g.
wheat, it is improbable that they would continue to be sticky. It is because of
money's other characteristics¾those, especially,
which make it liquid¾that wages, when fixed
in terms of it, tend to be sticky.[1]
(c) Thirdly, we come to what is the most fundamental
consideration in this context, namely, the characteristics of money which
satisfy liquidity-preference. For, in certain circumstances such as will often
occur, these will cause the rate of interest to be insensitive, particularly
below a certain figure,[2] even to a substantial increase in the quantity of money in proportion to
other forms of wealth. In other words, beyond a certain point money's yield from
liquidity does not fall in response to an increase in its quantity to anything
approaching the extent to which the yield from other types of assets falls when
their quantity is comparably increased.
In this connection the low (or negligible) carrying-costs of money play an
essential part. For if its carrying costs were material, they would offset the
effect of expectations as to the prospective value of money at future dates. The
readiness of the public to increase its [RES] stock of money in response
to a comparatively small stimulus is due to the advantages of liquidity (real or
supposed) having no offset to contend with in the shape of carrying-costs
mounting steeply with the lapse of time. In the case of a commodity other than
money a modest stock of it may offer some convenience to users of the commodity.
But even though a larger stock might have some attractions as representing a
store of wealth of stable value, this would be offset by its carrying-costs in
the shape of storage, wastage, etc.[p.234] Hence, after a certain point
is reached, there is necessarily a loss in holding a greater stock.
In the case of money, however, this, as we have seen, is not so,¾and
for a variety of reasons, namely, those which constitute money as being, in the
estimation of the public, par excellence "liquid". Thus those reformers,
who look for a remedy by creating artificial carrying-costs for money through
the device of requiring legal-tender currency to be periodically stamped at a
prescribed cost in order to retain its quality as money, or in analogous ways,
have been on the right track; and the practical value of their proposals
deserves consideration.
The significance of the money-rate of interest arises, therefore, out of the
combination of the characteristics that, through the working of the
liquidity-motive, this rate of interest may be somewhat unresponsive to a change
in the proportion which the quantity of money bears to other forms of wealth
measured in money, and that money has (or may have) zero (or negligible)
elasticities both of production and of substitution. The first condition means
that demand may be predominantly directed to money, the second that when this
occurs labour cannot be employed in producing more money, and the third that
there is no mitigation at any point through some other factor being capable, if
it is sufficiently cheap, of doing money's duty equally well. The only relief ¾
apart
from changes in the marginal efficiency of capital ¾ can
come (so long as the propensity towards liquidity is unchanged) from an increase
in the quantity of money, or ¾ which is formally the
same thing ¾ a rise in the value of money which
enables a given quantity to provide increased money-services.
Thus a rise in the money-rate of interest retards the output of all the
objects of which the production is elastic without being capable of stimulating
the output of money (the production of which is, by hypothesis, [p.235]
perfectly inelastic). The money-rate of interest, by setting the pace for all
the other commodity-rates of interest, holds back investment in the production
of these other commodities without being capable of stimulating investment for
the production of money, which by hypothesis cannot be produced. Moreover, owing
to the elasticity of demand for liquid cash in terms of debts, a small change in
the conditions governing this demand may not much alter the money-rate of
interest, whilst (apart from official action) it is also impracticable, owing to
the inelasticity of the production of money, for natural forces to bring the
money-rate of interest down by affecting the supply side. In the case of an
ordinary commodity, the inelasticity of the demand for liquid stocks of it would
enable small changes on the demand side to bring its rate of interest up or down
with a rush, whilst the elasticity of its supply would also tend to prevent a
high premium on spot over forward delivery. Thus with other commodities left to
themselves, "natural forces," i.e. the ordinary forces of the market,
would tend to bring their rate of interest down until the emergence of full
employment had brought about for commodities generally the inelasticity of
supply which we have postulated as a normal characteristic of money. Thus in the
absence of money and in the absence ¾ we must, of
course, also suppose ¾ of any other commodity with the
assumed characteristics of money, the rates of interest would only reach
equilibrium when there is full employment. Unemployment develops, that is to
say, because people want the moon; ¾ men cannot be
employed when the object of desire (i.e. money) is something which cannot
be produced and the demand for which cannot be readily choked off. There is no
remedy but to persuade the public that green cheese is practically the same
thing and to have a green cheese factory (i.e. a central bank) under
public control.
It is interesting to notice that the characteristic [p.236] which has
been traditionally supposed to render gold especially suitable for use as the
standard of value, namely, its inelasticity of supply, turns out to be precisely
the characteristic which is at the bottom of the trouble.
Our conclusion can be stated in the most general form (taking the propensity
to consume as given) as follows. No further increase in the rate of investment
is possible when the greatest amongst the own-rates of own-interest of all
available assets is equal to the greatest amongst the marginal efficiencies of
all assets, measured in terms of the asset whose own-rate of own-interest is
greatest.
In a position of full employment this condition is necessarily satisfied. But
it may also be satisfied before full employment is reached, if there exists some
asset, having zero (or relatively small) elasticities of production and
substitution,[1] whose rate of interest
declines more closely, as output increases, than the marginal efficiencies of
capital-assets measured in terms of it.
IV
We have shown above that for a commodity to be the standard of value is not a
sufficient condition for that commodity's rate of interest to be the significant
rate of interest. It is, however, interesting to consider how far those
characteristics of money as we know it, which make the money-rate of interest
the significant rate, are bound up with money being the standard in which debts
and wages are usually fixed. The matter requires consideration under two
aspects.
In the first place, the fact that contracts are fixed, and wages are usually
somewhat stable, in terms of money unquestionably plays a large part in
attracting to money so high a liquidity-premium. The conveni-[p.237]ence
of holding assets in the same standard as that in which future liabilities may
fall due and in a standard in terms of which the future cost of living is
expected to be relatively stable, is obvious. At the same time the expectation
of relative stability in the future money-cost of output might not be
entertained with much confidence if the standard of value were a commodity with
a high elasticity of production. Moreover, the low carrying-costs of money as we
know it play quite as large a part as a high liquidity-premium in making the
money-rate of interest the significant rate. For what matters is the difference
between the liquidity-premium and the carrying-costs; and in the case of
most commodities, other than such assets as gold and silver and bank-notes, the
carrying-costs are at least as high as the liquidity-premium ordinarily
attaching to the standard in which contracts and wages are fixed, so that, even
if the liquidity-premium now attaching to (e.g.) sterling-money were to
be transferred to (e.g.) wheat, the wheat-rate of interest would still be
unlikely to rise above zero. It remains the case, therefore, that, whilst the
fact of contracts and wages being fixed in terms of money considerably enhances
the significance of the money-rate of interest, this circumstance is,
nevertheless, probably insufficient by itself to produce the observed
characteristics of the money-rate of interest.
The second point to be considered is more subtle. The normal expectation that
the value of output will be more stable in terms of money than in terms of any
other commodity, depends of course, not on wages being arranged in terms of
money, but on wages being relatively sticky in terms of money. What,
then, would the position be if wages were expected to be more sticky (i.e.
more stable) in terms of some one or more commodities other than money, than in
terms of [RES] money itself? Such an expectation requires, not only that
the costs of the commodity in question are expected to be relatively constant in
terms of the wage-unit for [p.238] a greater or smaller scale of output
both in the short and in the long period, but also that any surplus over the
current demand at cost-price can be taken into stock without cost, i.e.
that its liquidity-premium exceeds its carrying-costs (for, otherwise, since
there is no hope of profit from a higher price, the carrying of a stock must
necessarily involve a loss). If a commodity can be found to satisfy these
conditions, then, assuredly, it might be set up as a rival to money. Thus it is
not logically impossible that there should be a commodity in terms of which the
value of output is expected to be more stable than in terms of money. But it
does not seem probable that any such commodity exists.
I conclude, therefore, that the commodity, in terms of which wages are
expected to be most sticky, cannot be one whose elasticity of production is not
least, and for which the excess of carrying-costs over liquidity-premium is not
least. In other words, the expectation of a relative stickiness of wages in
terms of money is a corollary of the excess of liquidity-premium over
carrying-costs being greater for money than for any other asset.
Thus we see that the various characteristics, which combine to make the
money-rate of interest significant, interact with one another in a cumulative
fashion. The fact that money has low elasticities of production and substitution
and low carrying-costs tends to raise the expectation that money-wages will be
relatively stable; and this expectation enhances money's liquidity-premium and
prevents the exceptional correlation between the money-rate of interest and the
marginal efficiencies of other assets which might, if it could exist, rob the
money-rate of interest of its sting.
Professor Pigou (with others) has been
accustomed to assume that there is a presumption in favour of real wages being
more stable than money-wages. But this could only be the case if there were a
presumption in [p.239] favour of stability of employment. Moreover, there
is also the difficulty that wage-goods have a high carrying-cost. If, indeed,
some attempt were made to stabilise real wages by fixing wages in terms of
wage-goods, the effect could only be to cause a violent oscillation of
money-prices. For every small fluctuation in the propensity to consume and the
inducement to invest would cause money-prices to rush violently between zero and
infinity. That money-wages should be more stable than real wages is a condition
of the system possessing inherent stability.
Thus the attribution of relative stability to real wages is not merely a
mistake in fact and experience. It is also a mistake in logic, if we are
supposing that the system in view is stable, in the sense that small changes in
the propensity to consume and the inducement to invest do not produce violent
effects on prices.
V
As a footnote to the above, it may be worth emphasising what has been already
stated above, namely, that "liquidity" and "carrying-costs" are both a matter of
degree; and that it is only in having the former high relatively to the latter
that the peculiarity of "money" consists.
Consider, for example, an economy in which there is no asset for which the
liquidity-premium is always in excess of the carrying-costs; which is the best
definition I can give of a so-called "non-monetary" economy. There exists
nothing, that is to say, but particular consumables and particular capital
equipments more or less differentiated according to the character of the
consumables which they can yield up, or assist to yield up, over a greater or a
shorter period of time; all of which, unlike cash, deteriorate or involve
expense, if they are kept in stock, to a value in excess of any
liquidity-premium which may attach to them.[p.240]
In such an economy capital equipments will differ from one another (a)
in the variety of the consumables in the production of which they are capable of
assisting, (b) in the stability of value of their output (in the sense in
which the value of bread is more stable through time than the value of
fashionable novelties), and (c) in the rapidity with which the wealth
embodied in them can become "liquid", in the sense of producing output, the
proceeds of which can be re-embodied if desired in quite a different form.
The owners of wealth will then weigh the lack of "liquidity" of different
capital equipments in the above sense as a medium in which to hold wealth
against the best available actuarial estimate of their prospective yields after
allowing for risk. The liquidity-premium, it will be observed, is partly similar
to the risk-premium, but partly different;¾the
difference corresponding to the difference between the best estimates we can
make of probabilities and the confidence with which we make them.[1]
When we were dealing, in earlier chapters, with the estimation of prospective
yield, we did not enter into detail as to how the estimation is made: and to
avoid complicating the argument, we did not distinguish differences in liquidity
from differences in risk proper. It is evident, however, that in calculating the
own-rate of interest we must allow for both.
There is, clearly, no absolute standard of "liquidity" but merely a scale of
liquidity¾a varying premium of which account has to
be taken, in addition to the yield of use and the carrying-costs, in estimating
the comparative attractions of holding different forms of wealth. The conception
of what contributes to "liquidity" is a partly vague one, changing from time to
time and depending on social practices and institutions. The order of preference
in the minds of owners of wealth in which at any given time they express their
feelings about liquidity is, however, definite and is all we require [p.241]
for our analysis of the behaviour of the economic system.
It may be that in certain historic environments the possession of land has
been characterised by a high liquidity-premium in the minds of owners of wealth;
and since land resembles money in that its elasticities of production and
substitution may be very low,[1]
it is conceivable that there have been occasions in history in which the desire
to hold land has played the same rôle in keeping up the rate of interest at too
high a level which money has played in recent times. It is difficult to trace
this influence quantitatively owing to the absence of a forward price for land
in terms of itself which is strictly comparable with the rate of interest on a
money debt. We have, however, something which has, at times, been closely
analogous, in the shape of high rates of interest on mortgages.[2]
The high rates of interest from mortgages on land, often exceeding the probable
net yield from cultivating the land, have been a familiar feature of many
agricultural economies. Usury laws have been directed primarily against
encumbrances of this character. And rightly so. For in earlier social
organisation where long-term bonds in the modern sense were non-existent, the
competition of a high interest-rate on mortgages may well have had the same
effect in retarding the growth of wealth from current investment in newly
produced capital-assets, as high interest rates on long-term debts have had in
more recent times. [p.242]
That the world after several millennia of steady individual saving, is so
poor as it is in accumulated capital-assets, is to be explained, in my opinion,
neither by the improvident propensities of mankind, nor even by the destruction
of war, but by the high liquidity-premiums formerly attaching to the ownership
of land and now attaching to money. I differ in this from the older view as
expressed by Marshall with an unusual
dogmatic force in his Principles of Economics, p. 581:
Everyone is aware that the accumulation of wealth is held in check, and the
rate of interest so far sustained, by the preference which the great mass of
humanity have for present over deferred gratifications, or, in other words, by
their unwillingness to "wait".
VI
In my Treatise on Money I defined what purported to be a unique rate
of interest, which I called the natural rate of interest¾namely,
the rate of interest which, in the terminology of my Treatise, preserved
equality between the rate of saving (as there defined) and the rate of
investment. I believed this to be a development and clarification of Wicksell's
"natural rate of interest", which was, according to him, the rate which would
preserve the stability of some, not quite clearly specified, price-level.
I had, however, overlooked the fact that in any given society there is, on
this definition, a different natural rate of interest for each
hypothetical level of employment. And, similarly, for every rate of interest
there is a level of employment for which that rate is the "natural" rate, in the
sense that the system will be in equilibrium with that rate of interest and that
level of employment. Thus it was a mistake to speak of the natural rate
of interest or to suggest that the above definition would yield a unique value
for the rate of interest irrespective of the level of employment. I had [p.243]
not then understood that, in certain conditions, the system could be in
equilibrium with less than full employment.
I am now no longer of the opinion that the concept of a "natural" rate of
interest, which previously seemed to me a most promising idea, has anything very
useful or significant to contribute to our analysis. It is merely the rate of
interest which will preserve the status quo; and, in general, we have no
predominant interest in the status quo as such.
If there is any such rate of interest, which is unique and significant, it
must be the rate which we might term the neutral rate of interest,[1]
namely, the natural rate in the above sense which is consistent with full employment,
given the other parameters of the system; though this rate might be better
described, perhaps, as the optimum rate.
The neutral rate of interest can be more strictly defined as the rate of
interest which prevails in equilibrium when output and employment are such that
the elasticity of employment as a whole is zero.[2]
The above gives us, once again, the answer to the question as to what tacit
assumption is required to make sense of the classical theory of the rate of
interest. This theory assumes either that the actual rate of interest is always
equal to the neutral rate of interest in the sense in which we have just defined
the latter, or alternatively that the actual rate of interest is always equal to
the rate of interest which will maintain employment at some specified constant
level. If the traditional theory is thus interpreted, there is little or nothing
in its practical conclusions to which we need take exception. The classical
theory assumes that the banking authority or natural forces cause the
market-rate of interest to [p.244] satisfy one or other of the above
conditions; and it investigates what laws will govern the application and
rewards of the community's productive resources subject to this assumption. With
this limitation in force, the volume of output depends solely on the assumed
constant level of employment in conjunction with the current equipment and
technique; and we are safely ensconced in a Ricardian
world.
Footnotes: [p.230] 1 -
See Chapter 20. [back to text]
[p.232] 1 - This is a matter which
will be examined in greater detail in Chapter 19 below.
[back to text]
[p.233] 1 - If wages (and contracts)
were fixed in terms of wheat, it might be that wheat would acquire some of
money's liquidity-premium;¾ we will return to this
question in (iv) below. [back to text]
[p.233] 2 - See p.172
above [back to text]
[p.236] 1 - A zero
elasticity is a more stringent condition than is necessarily required. [back to text]
[p.240] 1 - Cf. the footnote
to p.148 above. [back to text]
[p.241] 1 - The attribute of
"liquidity" is by no means independent of the presence of these two
characteristics. For it is unlikely that an asset, of which the supply can
be easily increased or the desire for which can be easily diverted by a change
in relative price, will possess the attribute of "liquidity" in the
minds of owners of wealth. Money itself rapidly loses the attribute of
"liquidity" if its future supply is expected to undergo sharp
changes. [back to text]
[p.241] 2 - A
mortgage and the interest thereon are, indeed, fixed in terms of money.
But the fact that the mortgagor has the option to deliver the land itself in
discharge of the debt
¾ and must so deliver it if he cannot find the money
on demand ¾ has sometimes made the mortgage system
approximate to a contract of land for future delivery against land for spot
delivery. There have been sales of lands to tenants against mortgages
effected by them, which, in fact, came very near to being transactions of this
character. [back to text]
[p.243] 1 - This definition does
not correspond to any of the various definitions of neutral money given
by recent writers; though it may, perhaps, have some relation to the objective
which these writers have had in mind. [back to text]
[p.243] 2 - Cf. Chapter
20 below. [back to text]
|