[p.194]
Chapter 15
THE PSYCHOLOGICAL AND BUSINESS INCENTIVES
TO LIQUIDITY
I
We must now develop in more detail the analysis of the motives to
liquidity-preference which were introduced in a preliminary way in Chapter
13. The subject is substantially the same as that which has been sometimes
discussed under the heading of the Demand for Money. It is also closely
connected with what is called the income-velocity of money;¾for
the income-velocity of money merely measures what proportion of their incomes
the public chooses to hold in cash, so that an increased income-velocity of
money may be a symptom of a decreased liquidity-preference. It is not the same
thing, however, since it is in respect of his stock of accumulated savings,
rather than of his income, that the individual can exercise his choice between
liquidity and illiquidity. And, anyhow, the term "income-velocity of money"
carries with it the misleading suggestion of a presumption in favour of the
demand for money as a whole being proportional, or having some determinate
relation, to income, whereas this presumption should apply, as we shall see,
only to a portion of the public's cash holdings; with the result that it
overlooks the part played by the rate of interest.
In my Treatise on Money I studied the total demand for money under the
headings of income-deposits, [p.195] business-deposits, and
savings-deposits, and I need not repeat here the analysis which I gave in
Chapter 3 of that book. Money held for each of the three purposes forms,
nevertheless, a single pool, which the holder is under no necessity to segregate
into three water-tight compartments; for they need not be sharply divided even
in his own mind, and the same sum can be held primarily for one purpose and
secondarily for another. Thus we can¾equally well,
and, perhaps, better¾consider the individual's
aggregate demand for money in given circumstances as a single decision, though
the composite result of a number of different motives.
In analysing the motives, however, it is still convenient to classify them
under certain headings, the first of which broadly corresponds to the former
classification of income-deposits and business-deposits, and the two latter to
that of savings-deposits. These I have briefly introduced in Chapter
13 under the headings of the transactions-motive, which can be further
classified as the income-motive and the business-motive, the
precautionary-motive and the speculative-motive.
(i) The Income-motive. One reason for holding cash is to
bridge the interval between the receipt of income and its disbursement. The
strength of this motive in inducing a decision to hold a given aggregate of cash
will chiefly depend on the amount of income and the normal length of the
interval between its receipt and its disbursement. It is in this connection that
the concept of the income-velocity of money is strictly appropriate.
(ii) The Business-motive. Similarly, cash is held to bridge
the interval between the time of incurring business costs and that of the
receipt of the sale-proceeds; cash held by dealers to bridge the interval
between purchase and realisation being included under this heading. The strength
of this demand will chiefly depend on the value of current output (and hence on [p.196]
current income), and on the number of hands through which output passes.
(iii) The Precautionary-motive. To provide for
contingencies requiring sudden expenditure and for unforeseen opportunities of
advantageous purchases, and also to hold an asset of which the value is fixed in
terms of money to meet a subsequent liability fixed in terms of money, are
further motives for holding cash.
The strength of all these three types of motive will partly depend on the
cheapness and the reliability of methods of obtaining cash, when it is required,
by some form of temporary borrowing, in particular by overdraft or its
equivalent. For there is no necessity to hold idle cash to bridge over intervals
if it can be obtained without difficulty at the moment when it is actually
required. Their strength will also depend on what we may term the relative cost
of holding cash. If the cash can only be retained by forgoing the purchase of a
profitable asset, this increases the cost and thus weakens the motive towards
holding a given amount of cash. If deposit interest is earned or if bank charges
are avoided by holding cash, this decreases the cost and strengthens the motive.
It may be, however, that this is likely to be a minor factor except where large
changes in the cost of holding cash are in question.
(iv) There remains the Speculative-motive. This needs a
more detailed examination than the others, both because it is less well
understood and because it is particularly important in transmitting the effects
of a change in the quantity of money.
In normal circumstances the amount of money required to satisfy the
transactions-motive and the precautionary-motive is mainly a resultant of the
general activity of the economic system and of the level of money-income. But it
is by playing on the speculative-motive that monetary management (or, in the
absence of management, chance changes in the quantity of money) is brought to
bear on the economic [p.197] system. For the demand for money to satisfy
the former motives is generally irresponsive to any influence except the actual
occurrence of a change in the general economic activity and the level of
incomes; whereas experience indicates that the aggregate demand for money to
satisfy the speculative-motive usually shows a continuous response to gradual
changes in the rate of interest, i.e. there is a continuous curve
relating changes in the demand for money to satisfy the speculative motive and
changes in the rate of interest as given by changes in the prices of bonds and
debts of various maturities.
Indeed, if this were not so, "open market operations" would be impracticable.
I have said that experience indicates the continuous relationship stated above,
because in normal circumstances the banking system is in fact always able to
purchase (or sell) bonds in exchange for cash by bidding the price of bonds up
(or down) in the market by a modest amount; and the larger the quantity of cash
which they seek to create (or cancel) by purchasing (or selling) bonds and
debts, the greater must be the fall (or rise) in the rate of interest. Where,
however, (as in the United States, 1933-1934)
open-market operations have been limited to the purchase of very short-dated
securities, the effect may, of course, be mainly confined to the very short-term
rate of interest and have but little reaction on the much more important
long-term rates of interest.
In dealing with the speculative-motive it is, however, important to
distinguish between the changes in the rate of interest which are due to changes
in the supply of money available to satisfy the speculative-motive, without
there having been any change in the liquidity function, and those which are
primarily due to changes in expectation affecting the liquidity function itself.
Open-market operations may, indeed, influence the rate of interest through both
channels; since they may not only change the volume of [p.198] money, but
may also give rise to changed expectations concerning the future policy of the Central
Bank or of the Government. Changes in the liquidity function itself; due to a
change in the news which causes revision of expectations, will often be
discontinuous, and will, therefore, give rise to a corresponding discontinuity
of change in the rate of interest. Only, indeed, in so far as the change in the
news is differently interpreted by different individuals or affects individual
interests differently will there be room for any increased activity of dealing
in the bond market. If the change in the news affects the judgment and the
requirements of everyone in precisely the same way, the rate of interest (as
indicated by the prices of bonds and debts) will be adjusted forthwith to the
new situation without any market transactions being necessary.
Thus, in the simplest case, where everyone is similar and similarly placed, a
change in circumstances or expectations will not be capable of causing any
displacement of money whatever;¾it will simply
change the rate of interest in whatever degree is necessary to offset the desire
of each individual, felt at the previous rate, to change his holding of cash in
response to the new circumstances or expectations; and, since everyone will
change his ideas as to the rate which would induce him to alter his holdings of
cash in the same degree, no transactions will result. To each set of
circumstances and expectations there will correspond an appropriate rate of
interest, and there will never be any question of anyone changing his usual
holdings of cash.
In general, however, a change in circumstances or expectations will cause
some realignment in individual holdings of money;¾since,
in fact, a change will influence the ideas of different individuals differently
by reasons partly of differences in environment and the reason for which money
is held and partly of differences in knowledge and interpretation of the [p.199]
new situation. Thus the new equilibrium rate of interest will be associated with
a redistribution of money-holdings. Nevertheless it is the change in the rate of
interest, rather than the redistribution of cash, which deserves our main
attention. The latter is incidental to individual differences, whereas the
essential phenomenon is that which occurs in the simplest case. Moreover, even
in the general case, the shift in the rate of interest is usually the most
prominent part of the reaction to a change in the news. The movement in
bond-prices is, as the newspapers are accustomed to say, "out of all proportion
to the activity of dealing";¾which is as it should
be, in view of individuals being much more similar than they are dissimilar in
their reaction to news.
II
Whilst the amount of cash which an individual decides to hold to satisfy the
transactions-motive and the precautionary-motive is not entirely independent of
what he is holding to satisfy the speculative-motive, it is a safe first
approximation to regard the amounts of these two sets of cash-holdings as being
largely independent of one another. Let us, therefore, for the purposes of our
further analysis, break up our problem in this way.
Let the amount of cash held to satisfy the transactions- and
precautionary-motives be M1, and the amount held to satisfy
the speculative-motive be M2. Corresponding to these two
compartments of cash, we then have two liquidity functions L1
and L2. L1 mainly depends on the level
of income, whilst L2 mainly depends on the relation between
the current rate of interest and the state of expectation. Thus
M = M1 + M2 = L1(Y) + L2(r),
where L1 is the liquidity function corresponding to [p.200]
in income Y, which determines M1, and L2
is the liquidity function of the rate of interest r, which determines M2.
It follows that there are three matters to investigate: (i) the relation of
changes in M to Y and r, (ii) what determines the shape of L1,
(iii) what determines the shape of L2.
(i) The relation of changes in M to Y and r
depends, in the first instance, on the way in which changes in M come
about. Suppose that M consists of gold coins and that changes in M
can only result from increased returns to the activities of gold-miners who
belong to the economic system under examination. In this case changes in M
are, in the first instance, directly associated with changes in Y, since
the new gold accrues as someone's income. Exactly the same conditions
hold if changes in M are due to the Government printing money wherewith
to meet its current expenditure;¾in this case also
the new money accrues as someone's income. The new level of income, however,
will not continue sufficiently high for the requirements of M1
to absorb the whole of the increase in M; and some portion of the money
will seek an outlet in buying securities or other assets until r has
fallen so as to bring about an increase in the magnitude of M2
and at the same time to stimulate a rise in Y to such an extent that the
new money is absorbed either in M2 or in the M1
which corresponds to the rise in Y caused by the fall in r. Thus
at one remove this case comes to the same thing as the alternative case, where
the new money can only be issued in the first instance by a relaxation of the
conditions of credit by the banking system, so as to induce someone to sell the
banks a debt or a bond in exchange for the new cash.
It will, therefore, be safe for us to take the latter case as typical. A
change in M can be assumed to operate by changing r, and a change
in r will lead to a new equilibrium partly by changing M2
and partly [p.201] by changing Y and therefore M1.
The division of the increment of cash between M1 and M2
in the new position of equilibrium will depend on the responses of investment to
a reduction in the rate of interest and of income to an increase in investment. [1]
Since Y partly depends on r, it follows that a given change in M
has to cause a sufficient change in r for the resultant changes in M1
and M2 respectively to add up to the given change in M.
(ii) It is not always made clear whether the income-velocity of
money is defined as the ratio of Y to M or as the ratio of Y
to M1. I propose, however, to take it in the latter sense.
Thus if V is the income-velocity of money,
Y
L1(Y) = ¾¾ = M1.
V
There is, of course, no reason for supposing that V is constant. Its
value will depend on the character of banking and industrial organisation, on
social habits, on the distribution of income between different classes and on
the effective cost of holding idle cash. Nevertheless, if we have a short period
of time in view and can safely assume no material change in any of these
factors, we can treat V as nearly enough constant.
(iii) Finally there is the question of the relation between M2
and r. We have seen in Chapter 13 that uncertainty
as to the future course of the rate of interest is the sole intelligible
explanation of the type of liquidity-preference L2 which leads
to the holding of cash M2. It follows that a given M2
will not have a definite quantitative relation to a given rate of interest of r;¾what
matters is not the absolute level of r but the degree of its
divergence from what is considered a fairly safe level of r,
having regard to those calculations of probability which are being relied on.
Nevertheless, there are two reasons for expecting that, in [p.202] any
given state of expectation, a fall in r will be associated with an
increase in M2. In the first place, if the general view as to
what is a safe level of r is unchanged, every fall in r reduces
the market rate relatively to the "safe" rate and therefore increases the risk
of illiquidity; and, in the second place, every fall in r reduces the
current earnings from illiquidity, which are available as a sort of insurance
premium to offset the risk of loss on capital account, by an amount equal to the
difference between the squares of the old rate of interest and the new.
For example, if the rate of interest on a long-term debt is 4 per cent., it is
preferable to sacrifice liquidity unless on a balance of probabilities it is
feared that the long-term rate of interest may rise faster than by 4 per cent.
of itself per annum, i.e. by an amount greater than 0.16 per cent. per
annum. If, however, the rate of interest is already as low as 2 per cent., the
running yield will only offset a rise in it of as little as 0.04 per cent. per
annum. This, indeed, is perhaps the chief obstacle to a fall in the rate of
interest to a very low level. Unless reasons are believed to exist why future
experience will be very different from past experience, a long-term rate of
interest of (say) 2 per cent. leaves more to fear than to hope, and offers, at
the same time, a running yield which is only sufficient to offset a very small
measure of fear.
It is evident, then, that the rate of interest is a highly psychological
phenomenon. We shall find, indeed, in Book V. that it
cannot be in equilibrium at a level below the rate which corresponds to
full employment; because at such a level a state of true inflation will be
produced, with the result that M1 will absorb ever-increasing
quantities of cash. But at a level above the rate which corresponds to
full employment, the long-term market-rate of interest will depend, not only on
the current policy of the monetary authority, but also on market expectations
concerning its future policy. The [p.203] short-term rate of interest is
easily controlled by the monetary authority, both because it is not difficult to
produce a conviction that its policy will not greatly change in the very near
future, and also because the possible loss is small compared with the running
yield (unless it is approaching vanishing point). But the long-term rate may be
more recalcitrant when once it has fallen to a level which, on the basis of past
experience and present expectations of future monetary policy, is
considered "unsafe" by representative opinion. For example, in a country linked
to an international gold standard, a rate of interest lower than prevails
elsewhere will be viewed with a justifiable lack of confidence; yet a domestic
rate of interest dragged up to a parity with the highest rate (highest
after allowing for risk) prevailing in any country belonging to the
international system may be much higher than is consistent with domestic full
employment.
Thus a monetary policy which strikes public opinion as being experimental in
character or easily liable to change may fail in its objective of greatly
reducing the long-term rate of interest, because M2 may tend
to increase almost without limit in response to a reduction of r below a
certain figure. The same policy, on the other hand, may prove easily successful
if it appeals to public opinion as being reasonable and practicable and in the
public interest, rooted in strong conviction, and promoted by an authority
unlikely to be superseded.
It might be more accurate, perhaps, to say that the rate of interest is a
highly conventional, rather than a highly psychological, phenomenon. For its
actual value is largely governed by the prevailing view as to what its value is
expected to be. Any level of interest which is accepted with sufficient
conviction as likely to be durable will be durable; subject, of
course, in a changing society to fluctuations for all kinds of reasons round the
expected normal. In particular, when M1[p.204] is
increasing faster than M, the rate of interest will rise, and vice
versa. But it may fluctuate for decades about a level which is chronically
too high for full employment;¾particularly if it is
the prevailing opinion that the rate of interest is self-adjusting, so that the
level established by convention is thought to be rooted in objective grounds
much stronger than convention, the failure of employment to attain an optimum
level being in no way associated, in the minds either of the public or of
authority, with the prevalence of an inappropriate range of rates of interest.
The difficulties in the way of maintaining effective demand at a level high
enough to provide full employment, which ensue from the association of a
conventional and fairly stable long-term rate of interest with a fickle and
highly unstable marginal efficiency of capital, should be, by now, obvious to
the reader.
Such comfort as we can fairly take from more encouraging reflections must be
drawn from the hope that, precisely because the convention is not rooted in
secure knowledge, it will not be always unduly resistant to a modest measure of
persistence and consistency of purpose by the monetary authority. Public opinion
can be fairly rapidly accustomed to a modest fall in the rate of interest and
the conventional expectation of the future may be modified accordingly; thus
preparing the way for a further movement¾up to a
point. The fall in the long-term rate of interest in Great Britain after her
departure from the gold standard provides an interesting example of this;¾the
major movements were effected by a series of discontinuous jumps, as the
liquidity function of the public, having become accustomed to each successive
reduction, became ready to respond to some new incentive in the news or in the
policy of the authorities. [p.205]
III
We can sum up the above in the proposition that in any given state of
expectation there is in the minds of the public a certain potentiality towards
holding cash beyond what is required by the transactions-motive or the
precautionary-motive, which will realise itself in actual cash-holdings in a
degree which depends on the terms on which the monetary authority is willing to
create cash. It is this potentiality which is summed up in the liquidity
function L2.
Corresponding to the quantity of money created by the monetary authority,
there will, therefore, be cet. par. a determinate rate of interest or,
more strictly, a determinate complex of rates of interest for debts of different
maturities. The same thing, however, would be true of any other factor in the
economic system taken separately. Thus this particular analysis will only be
useful and significant in so far as there is some specially direct or purposive
connection between changes in the quantity of money and changes in the rate of
interest. Our reason for supposing that there is such a special connection
arises from the fact that, broadly speaking, the banking system and the monetary
authority are dealers in money and debts and not in assets or consumables.
If the monetary authority were prepared to deal both ways on specified terms
in debts of all maturities, and even more so if it were prepared to deal in
debts of varying degrees of risk, the relationship between the complex of rates
of interest and the quantity of money would be direct. The complex of rates of
interest would simply be an expression of the terms on which the banking system
is prepared to acquire or part with debts; and the quantity of money would be
the amount which can find a home in the possession of individuals who¾after
taking account of all relevant circumstances¾prefer
the control of liquid cash to parting with it [p.206] in exchange for a
debt on the terms indicated by the market rate of interest. Perhaps a complex
offer by the central bank to buy and sell at stated prices gilt-edged bonds of
all maturities, in place of the single bank rate for short-term bills, is the
most important practical improvement which can be made in the technique of
monetary management.
To-day, however, in actual practice, the extent to which the price of debts
as fixed by the banking system is "effective" in the market, in the sense that
it governs the actual market-price, varies in different systems. Sometimes the
price is more effective in one direction than in the other; that is to say, the
banking system may undertake to purchase debts at a certain price but not
necessarily to sell them at a figure near enough to its buying-price to
represent no more than a dealer's turn, though there is no reason why the price
should not be made effective both ways with the aid of open-market operations.
There is also the more important qualification which arises out of the monetary
authority not being, as a rule, an equally willing dealer in debts of all
maturities. The monetary authority often tends in practice to concentrate upon
short-term debts and to leave the price of long-term debts to be influenced by
belated and imperfect reactions from the price of short-term debts;¾though
here again there is no reason why they need do so. Where these qualifications
operate, the directness of the relation between the rate of interest and the
quantity of money is correspondingly modified. In Great Britain the field of
deliberate control appears to be widening. But in applying this theory in any
particular case allowance must be made for the special characteristics of the
method actually employed by the monetary authority. If the monetary authority
deals only in short-term debts, we have to consider what influence the price,
actual and prospective, of short-term debts exercises on debts of longer
maturity. [p.207]
Thus there are certain limitations on the ability of the monetary authority
to establish any given complex of rates of interest for debts of different terms
and risks, which can be summed up as follows:
(1) There are those limitations which arise out of the monetary
authority's own practices in limiting its willingness to deal to debts of a
particular type.
(2) There is the possibility, for the reasons discussed above,
that, after the rate of interest has fallen to a certain level,
liquidity-preference may become virtually absolute in the sense that almost
everyone prefers cash to holding a debt which yields so low a rate of interest.
In this event the monetary authority would have lost effective control over the
rate of interest. But whilst this limiting case might become practically
important in future, I know of no example of it hitherto. Indeed, owing to the
unwillingness of most monetary authorities to deal boldly in debts of long term,
there has not been much opportunity for a test. Moreover, if such a situation
were to arise, it would mean that the public authority itself could borrow
through the banking system on an unlimited scale at a nominal rate of interest.
(3) The most striking examples of a complete breakdown of
stability in the rate of interest, due to the liquidity function flattening out
in one direction or the other, have occurred in very abnormal circumstances. In
Russia and Central Europe after the war a currency crisis or flight from the
currency was experienced, when no one could be induced to retain holdings either
of money or of debts on any terms whatever, and even a high and rising rate of
interest was unable to keep pace with the marginal efficiency of capital
(especially of stocks of liquid goods) under the influence of the expectation of
an ever greater fall in the value of money; whilst in the United States at
certain dates in 1932 there was a crisis of the opposite kind¾a
financial crisis or crisis of liquidation, when [p.208] scarcely anyone
could be induced to part with holdings of money on any reasonable terms.
(4) There is, finally, the difficulty discussed in section IV of Chapter
11, p. 144, in the way of bringing the effective rate of interest below
a certain figure, which may prove important in an era of low interest-rates;
namely the intermediate costs of bringing the borrower and the ultimate lender
together, and the allowance for risk, especially for moral risk, which the
lender requires over and above the pure rate of interest. As the pure rate of
interest declines it does not follow that the allowances for expense and risk
decline pari passu. Thus the rate of interest which the typical borrower
has to pay may decline more slowly than the pure rate of interest, and may be
incapable of being brought, by the methods of the existing banking and financial
organisation, below a certain minimum figure. This is particularly important if
the estimation of moral risk is appreciable. For where the risk is due to doubt
in the mind of the lender concerning the honesty of the borrower, there is
nothing in the mind of a borrower who does not intend to be dishonest to offset
the resultant higher charge. It is also important in the case of short-term
loans (e.g. bank loans) where the expenses are heavy;¾a
bank may have to charge its customers 1½ to 2 per cent., even if the pure rate
of interest to the lender is nil.
IV
At the cost of anticipating what is more properly the subject of Chapter
21 below it may be interesting briefly at this stage to indicate the
relationship of the above to the Quantity Theory of Money.
In a static society or in a society in which for any other reason no one
feels any uncertainty about the future rates of interest, the Liquidity Function
L2, or the propensity to hoard (as we might term it), will [p.209]
always be zero in equilibrium. Hence in equilibrium M2 = 0
and M = M1; so that any change in M
will cause the rate of interest to fluctuate until income reaches a level at
which the change in M1 is equal to the supposed change in M.
Now M1V = Y, where V
is the income-velocity of money as defined above and Y is the aggregate
income. Thus if it is practicable to measure the quantity, O, and the
price, P, of current output, we have Y = OP,
and, therefore, MV = OP; which is much the
same as the Quantity Theory of Money in its traditional form. [1]
For the purposes of the real world it is a great fault in the Quantity Theory
that it does not distinguish between changes in prices which are a function of
changes in output, and those which are a function of changes in the wage-unit.[2]
The explanation of this omission is, perhaps, to be found in the assumptions
that there is no propensity to hoard and that there is always full employment.
For in this case, O being constant and M2 being zero,
it follows, if we can take V also as constant, that both the wage-unit
and the price-level will be directly proportional to the quantity of money.
Footnotes: [p.201] 1 - We
must postpone to Book V. the question of what will
determine the character of the new equilibrium. [back to text]
[p.209] 1 - If we had
defined V, not as equal to Y/M1 but as equal to Y/M,
then, of course, the Quantity Theory is a truism which holds in all
circumstances, though without significance. [back to text]
[p.209] 2 - This point will be
further developed in Chapter 21 below. [back to text]
|