[p.165]
Chapter 13
THE GENERAL THEORY OF THE RATE OF INTEREST
I
We have shown in Chapter 11 that, whilst there are
forces causing the rate of investment to rise or fall so as to keep the marginal
efficiency of capital equal to the rate of interest, yet the marginal efficiency
of capital is, in itself; a different thing from the ruling rate of interest.
The schedule of the marginal efficiency of capital may be said to govern the
terms on which loanable funds are demanded for the purpose of new investment;
whilst the rate of interest governs the terms on which funds are being currently
supplied. To complete our theory, therefore, we need to know what determines the
rate of interest.
In Chapter 14 and its Appendix
we shall consider the answers to this question which have been given hitherto.
Broadly speaking, we shall find that they make the rate of interest to depend on
the interaction of the schedule of the marginal efficiency of capital with the
psychological propensity to save. But the notion that the rate of interest is
the balancing factor which brings the demand for saving in the shape of new
investment forthcoming at a given rate of interest into equality with the supply
of saving which results at that rate of interest from the community's
psychological propensity to save, breaks down as soon as we perceive that it is
impossible to deduce the rate of interest merely from a knowledge of these two
factors. [p.166]
What, then, is our own answer to this question?
II
The psychological time-preferences of an individual require two distinct sets
of decisions to carry them out completely. The first is concerned with that
aspect of time-preference which I have called the propensity to consume,
which, operating under the influence of the various motives set forth in Book
III, determines for each individual how much of his income he will consume
and how much he will reserve in some form of command over future
consumption.
But this decision having been made, there is a further decision which awaits
him, namely, in what form he will hold the command over future
consumption which he has reserved, whether out of his current income or from
previous savings. Does he want to hold it in the form of immediate, liquid
command (i.e. in money or its equivalent)? Or is he prepared to part with
immediate command for a specified or indefinite period, leaving it to future
market conditions to determine on what terms he can, if necessary, convert
deferred command over specific goods into immediate command over goods in
general? In other words, what is the degree of his liquidity-preference¾where
an individual's liquidity-preference is given by a schedule of the amounts of
his resources, valued in terms of money or of wage-units, which he will wish to
retain in the form of money in different sets of circumstances?
We shall find that the mistake in the accepted theories of the rate of
interest lies in their attempting to derive the rate of interest from the first
of these two constituents of psychological time-preference to the neglect of the
second; and it is this neglect which we must endeavour to repair.
It should be obvious that the rate of interest cannot [p.167] be a
return to saving or waiting as such. For if a man hoards his savings in cash, he
earns no interest, though he saves just as much as before. On the contrary, the
mere definition of the rate of interest tells us in so many words that the rate
of interest is the reward for parting with liquidity for a specified period. For
the rate of interest is, in itself; nothing more than the inverse proportion
between a sum of money and what can be obtained for parting with control over
the money in exchange for a debt [1]
for a stated period of time. [2]
Thus the rate of interest at any time, being the reward for parting with
liquidity, is a measure of the unwillingness of those who possess money to part
with their liquid control over it. The rate of interest is not the "price"
which brings into equilibrium the demand for resources to invest with the
readiness to abstain from present consumption. It is the "price" which
equilibrates the desire to hold wealth in the form of cash with the available
quantity of cash;¾which implies that if the rate of
interest were lower, i.e. if the reward for parting with cash were diminished,
the aggregate amount of cash which the public would wish to hold would exceed
the available supply, and that if the rate of interest were raised, there would
be a surplus of cash which no one would be willing to hold. If this explanation
is correct, the quantity of money is the [p.168] other factor, which, in
conjunction with liquidity-preference, determines the actual rate of interest in
given circumstances. Liquidity-preference is a potentiality or functional
tendency, which fixes the quantity of money which the public will hold when the
rate of interest is given; so that if r is the rate of interest, M
the quantity of money and L the function of liquidity-preference, we have
M = L(r). This is where, and how, the
quantity of money enters into the economic scheme.
At this point, however, let us turn back and consider why such a thing as
liquidity-preference exists. In this connection we can usefully employ the
ancient distinction between the use of money for the transaction of current
business and its use as a store of wealth. As regards the first of these two
uses, it is obvious that up to a point it is worth while to sacrifice a certain
amount of interest for the convenience of liquidity. But, given that the rate of
interest is never negative, why should anyone prefer to hold his wealth in a
form which yields little or no interest to holding it in a form which yields
interest (assuming, of course, at this stage, that the risk of default is the
same in respect of a bank balance as of a bond)? A full explanation is complex
and must wait for Chapter 15. There is, however, a
necessary condition failing which the existence of a liquidity-preference for
money as a means of holding wealth could not exist.
This necessary condition is the existence of uncertainty as to the
future of the rate of interest, i.e. as to the complex of rates of
interest for varying maturities which will rule at future dates. For if the
rates of interest ruling at all future times could be foreseen with certainty,
all future rates of interest could be inferred from the present rates of
interest for debts of different maturities, which would be adjusted to the
knowledge of the future rates. For example, if 1dr
is the value in the present year 1 of £1 deferred r years and it is [p.169]
known that ndr will be the value
in the year n of £1 deferred r years from that date, we have
1dn+r
ndr = ¾¾¾¾
;
1dn
whence it follows that the rate at which any debt can be turned into cash n
years hence is given by two out of the complex of current rates of interest. If
the current rate of interest is positive for debts of every maturity, it must
always be more advantageous to purchase a debt than to hold cash as a store of
wealth.
If, on the contrary, the future rate of interest is uncertain we cannot
safely infer that ndr will prove to
be equal to 1dn+r / 1dn when
the time comes. Thus if a need for liquid cash may conceivably arise before the
expiry of n years, there is a risk of a loss being incurred in purchasing
a long-term debt and subsequently turning it into cash, as compared with holding
cash. The actuarial profit or mathematical expectation of gain calculated in
accordance with the existing probabilities¾if it can
be so calculated, which is doubtful¾must be
sufficient to compensate for the risk of disappointment.
There is, moreover, a further ground for liquidity-preference which results
from the existence of uncertainty as to the future of the rate of interest,
provided that there is an organised market for dealing in debts. For different
people will estimate the prospects differently and anyone who differs from the
predominant opinion as expressed in market quotations may have a good reason for
keeping liquid resources in order to profit, if he is right, from its turning
out in due course that the 1dr's were in a
mistaken relationship to one another. [1]
This is closely analogous to what we have already [p.170] discussed at
some length in connection with the marginal efficiency of capital. Just as we
found that the marginal efficiency of capital is fixed, not by the "best"
opinion, but by the market valuation as determined by mass psychology, so also
expectations as to the future of the rate of interest as fixed by mass
psychology have their reactions on liquidity-preference;¾but
with this addition that the individual, who believes that future rates of
interest will be above the rates assumed by the market, has a reason for keeping
actual liquid cash, [1]
whilst the individual who differs from the market in the other direction will
have a motive for borrowing money for short periods in order to purchase debts
of longer term. The market price will be fixed at the point at which the sales
of the "bears" and the purchases of the "bulls" are balanced.
The three divisions of liquidity-preference which we have distinguished above
may be defined as depending on (i) the transactions-motive, i.e. the need
of cash for the current transaction of personal and business exchanges; (ii) the
precautionary-motive, i.e. the desire for security as to the future cash
equivalent of a certain proportion of total resources; and (iii) the
speculative-motive, i.e. the object of securing profit from knowing
better than the market what the future will bring forth. As when we were
discussing the marginal efficiency of capital, the question of the desirability
of having a highly organised market for dealing with debts presents us with a
dilemma. For, in the absence of an organised market, liquidity-preference due to
the precautionary-motive would be greatly increased; whereas the existence of an
organised market gives an [p.171] opportunity for wide fluctuations in
liquidity-preference due to the speculative-motive.
It may illustrate the argument to point out that, if the
liquidity-preferences due to the transactions-motive and the
precautionary-motive are assumed to absorb a quantity of cash which is not very
sensitive to changes in the rate of interest as such and apart from its
reactions on the level of income, so that the total quantity of money, less this
quantity, is available for satisfying liquidity-preferences due to the
speculative-motive, the rate of interest and the price of bonds have to be fixed
at the level at which the desire on the part of certain individuals to hold cash
(because at that level they feel "bearish" of the future of bonds) is exactly
equal to the amount of cash available for the speculative-motive. Thus each
increase in the quantity of money must raise the price of bonds sufficiently to
exceed the expectations of some "bull" and so influence him to sell his bond for
cash and join the "bear" brigade. If, however, there is a negligible demand for
cash from the speculative-motive except for a short transitional interval, an
increase in the quantity of money will have to lower the rate of interest almost
forthwith, in whatever degree is necessary to raise employment and the wage-unit
sufficiently to cause the additional cash to be absorbed by the
transactions-motive and the precautionary-motive.
As a rule, we can suppose that the schedule of liquidity-preference relating
the quantity of money to the rate of interest is given by a smooth curve which
shows the rate of interest falling as the quantity of money is increased. For
there are several different causes all leading towards this result.
In the first place, as the rate of interest falls, it is likely, cet. par.,
that more money will be absorbed by liquidity-preferences due to the
transactions-motive. For if the fall in the rate of interest increases the
national income, the amount of money which it is convenient to [p.172]
keep for transactions will be increased more or less proportionately to the
increase in income; whilst, at the same time, the cost of the convenience of
plenty of ready cash in terms of loss of interest will be diminished. Unless we
measure liquidity-preference in terms of wage-units rather than of money (which
is convenient in some contexts), similar results follow if the increased
employment ensuing on a fall in the rate of interest leads to an increase of
wages, i.e. to an increase in the money value of the wage-unit. In the
second place, every fall in the rate of interest may, as we have just seen,
increase the quantity of cash which certain individuals will wish to hold
because their views as to the future of the rate of interest differ from the
market views.
Nevertheless, circumstances can develop in which even a large increase in the
quantity of money may exert a comparatively small influence on the rate of
interest. For a large increase in the quantity of money may cause so much
uncertainty about the future that liquidity-preferences due to the
precautionary-motive [RES] may be strengthened; whilst opinion about the
future of the rate of interest may be so unanimous that a small change in
present rates may cause a mass movement into cash. It is interesting that the
stability of the system and its sensitiveness to changes in the quantity of
money should be so dependent on the existence of a variety of opinion
about what is uncertain. Best of all that we should know the future. But if not,
then, if we are to control the activity of the economic system by changing the
quantity of money, it is important that opinions should differ Thus this method
of control is more precarious in the United States, where everyone tends to hold
the same opinion at the same time, than in England where differences of opinion
are more usual. [p.173]
III
We have now introduced money into our causal nexus for the first time, and we
are able to catch a first glimpse of the way in which changes in the quantity of
money work their way into the economic system. If, however, we are tempted to
assert that money is the drink which stimulates the system to activity, we must
remind ourselves that there may be several slips between the cup and the lip.
For whilst an increase in the quantity of money may be expected, cet. par.,
to reduce the rate of interest, this will not happen if the
liquidity-preferences of the public are increasing more than the quantity of
money; and whilst a decline in the rate of interest may be expected, cet. par.,
to increase the volume of investment, this will not happen if the schedule of
the marginal efficiency of capital is falling more rapidly than the rate of
interest; and whilst an increase in the volume of investment may be expected, cet.
par., to increase employment, this may not happen if the propensity to
consume is falling off. Finally, if employment increases, prices will rise in a
degree partly governed by the shapes of the physical supply functions, and
partly by the liability of the wage-unit to rise in terms of money. And when
output has increased and prices have risen, the effect of this on
liquidity-preference will be to increase the quantity of money necessary to
maintain a given rate of interest.
IV
Whilst liquidity-preference due to the speculative-motive corresponds to what
in my Treatise on Money I called "the state of bearishness", it is by no
means the same thing. For "bearishness" is there defined as the functional
relationship, not between the rate of interest (or price of debts) and the
quantity of money, but between the price of assets and debts, taken together, [p.174]
and the quantity of money. This treatment, however, involved a confusion between
results due to a change in the rate of interest and those due to a change in the
schedule of the marginal efficiency of capital, which I hope I have here
avoided.
V
The concept of Hoarding may be regarded as a first approximation to
the concept of Liquidity-preference. Indeed if we were to substitute "propensity
to hoard" for "hoarding", it would come to substantially the same thing. But if
we mean by "hoarding" an actual increase in cash-holding, it is an incomplete
idea¾and seriously misleading if it causes us to
think of "hoarding" and "not-hoarding" as simple alternatives. For the decision
to hoard is not taken absolutely or without regard to the advantages offered for
parting with liquidity;¾it results from a balancing
of advantages, and we have, therefore, to know what lies in the other scale.
Moreover it is impossible for the actual amount of hoarding to change as a
result of decisions on the part of the public, so long as we mean by "hoarding"
the actual holding of cash. For the amount of hoarding must be equal to the
quantity of money (or¾on some definitions¾to
the quantity of money minus what is required to satisfy the
transactions-motive); and the quantity of money is not determined by the public.
All that the propensity of the public towards hoarding can achieve is to
determine the rate of interest at which the aggregate desire to hoard becomes
equal to the available cash. The habit of overlooking the relation of the rate
of interest to hoarding may be a part of the explanation why interest has been
usually regarded as the reward of not-spending, whereas in fact it is the reward
of not-hoarding.
Footnotes: [p.167] 1 -
Without disturbance to this definition, we can draw the line between
"money" and "debts" at whatever point is most convenient for
handling a particular problem. For example, we can treat as money
any command over general purchasing power which the owner has not parted with
for a period in excess of three months, and as debt what cannot be
recovered for a longer period than this; or we can substitute for "three
months" one month or three days or three hours or any other period; or we
can exclude from money whatever is not legal tender on the spot. It
is often convenient in practice to include in money time-deposits with
banks and, occasionally, even such instruments as (e.g.) treasury
bills. As a rule, I shall, as in my Treatise on Money, assume that
money is co-extensive with bank deposits. [back to text]
[p.167] 2 - In general discussion, as
distinct from specific problems where the period of the debt is expressly
specified, it is convenient to mean by the rate of interest the complex of the
various rates of interest current for different periods of time, i.e. for
debts of different maturities. [back to text] [p.169]
1 - This is the same points as I
discussed in my Treatise on Money under the designation of the two views
and the "bull-bear" position. [back to text] [p.170]
1 - It might be thought that, in the same
way, and individual who believed that the prospective yield of investments will
be below what the market is expecting, will have a sufficient reason for holding
liquid cash. But this is not the case. He has a sufficient reason
for holding cash or debts in preference to equities; but the purchase of debts
will be a preferable alternative to holding cash, unless he also believes that
the future rate of interest will prove to be higher than the market is
supposing.[ back to text]
|